Philosophy

6 pages essay from just uploaded files due tuesday

1

INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY

Writing Assignment Guidelines

Format: I will only accept hardcopies.

Hard Deadline: August 2, 2018

This is not a research assignment. All the material for the successful completion of the assignment has

been covered in class. There are also notes available on the material available on Moodle.

Please do not plagiarize.

Topic: Explain in detail Descartes argument in the first Three Meditations. You paper should explain

Descartes goal in the Meditations, the dream argument, the demon hypothesis, the self as certain

foundation, the causal proof for the existence of God and so forth.

The assignment falls into four sections:

I. Introduction

What is Descartes primary goal in the Meditations?

What method does he utilize to achieve his goal? How specifically does the method work?

II. Doubt

What is the dream argument?

What is Descartes’ purpose in presenting it?

Why is the dream argument not enough? What is the demon hypothesis?

III. Certainty

Why does Descartes believe that he cannot be mistaken about everything?

What is the certain foundation?

To what does ‘I’ refer?

What is the essential property of the ‘I’?

What does it mean to say that ‘I exist’ is both clear and distinct?

What is the ‘wax example’ and what point is Descartes attempting to do with that argument?

2

IV. God

How does Descartes go about showing that something exists that is external to him and greater

than him?

What is the idea of God?

What are the main elements of the causal proof?

What are the ramifications of the proof for the demon hypothesis, and the status of

mathematical truth?

Meditations on First Philosophy
in which are demonstrated the existence of God and the distinction between

the human soul and body

René Descartes

Copyright ©

2

0

1

0–201

5

All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett

[Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as
though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations,
are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . . . . indicates
the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth.—In his title for this work,
Descartes is following a tradition (started by Aristotle) which uses ‘first philosophy’ as a label for metaphysics.

First launched: July 200

4

Last amended: April 200

7

Contents

  • First Meditation
  • 1

  • Second Meditation
  • 3

    Third Meditation 9

    Fourth Meditation 17

    Fifth Meditation 23

    Sixth Meditation 27

    Meditations René Descartes First Meditation

    First Meditation:
    On what can be called into doubt

    Some years ago I was struck by how many false things I
    had believed, and by how doubtful was the structure of
    beliefs that I had based on them. I realized that if I wanted
    to establish anything in the sciences that was stable and
    likely to last, I needed—just once in my life—to demolish
    everything completely and start again from the foundations.
    It looked like an enormous task, and I decided to wait until
    I was old enough to be sure that there was nothing to be
    gained from putting it off any longer. I have now delayed
    it for so long that I have no excuse for going on planning
    to do it rather than getting to work. So today I have set all
    my worries aside and arranged for myself a clear stretch of
    free time. I am here quite alone, and at last I will devote
    myself, sincerely and without holding back, to demolishing
    my opinions.

    I can do this without showing that all my beliefs are false,
    which is probably more than I could ever manage. My reason
    tells me that as well as withholding assent from propositions
    that are obviously •false, I should also withhold it from ones
    that are •not completely certain and indubitable. So all I
    need, for the purpose of rejecting all my opinions, is to find
    in each of them at least some reason for doubt. I can do
    this without going through them one by one, which would
    take forever: once the foundations of a building have been
    undermined, the rest collapses of its own accord; so I will
    go straight for the basic principles on which all my former
    beliefs rested.

    Whatever I have accepted until now as most true has
    come to me through my senses. But occasionally I have
    found that they have deceived me, and it is unwise to trust

    completely those who have deceived us even once.
    [The next paragraph presents a series of considerations back and

    forth. It is set out here as a discussion between two people, but that isn’t

    how Descartes presented it.]
    Hopeful: Yet although the senses sometimes deceive us

    about objects that are very small or distant, that doesn’t
    apply to my belief that I am here, sitting by the fire, wearing
    a winter dressing-gown, holding this piece of paper in my
    hands, and so on. It seems to be quite impossible to doubt
    beliefs like these, which come from the senses. Another
    example: how can I doubt that these hands or this whole
    body are mine? To doubt such things I would have to liken
    myself to brain-damaged madmen who are convinced they
    are kings when really they are paupers, or say they are
    dressed in purple when they are naked, or that they are
    pumpkins, or made of glass. Such people are insane, and I
    would be thought equally mad if I modelled myself on them.

    Doubtful (sarcastically): What a brilliant piece of reason-
    ing! As if I were not a man who sleeps at night and often has
    all the same experiences while asleep as madmen do when
    awake—indeed sometimes even more improbable ones. Often
    in my dreams I am convinced of just such familiar events—
    that I am sitting by the fire in my dressing-gown—when in
    fact I am lying undressed in bed!

    Hopeful: Yet right now my eyes are certainly wide open
    when I look at this piece of paper; I shake my head and it
    isn’t asleep; when I rub one hand against the other, I do it
    deliberately and know what I am doing. This wouldn’t all
    happen with such clarity to someone asleep.

    1

    Meditations René Descartes First Meditation

    Doubtful: Indeed! As if I didn’t remember other occasions
    when I have been tricked by exactly similar thoughts while
    asleep! As I think about this more carefully, I realize that
    there is never any reliable way of distinguishing being awake
    from being asleep. This discovery makes me feel dizzy, [joke:]
    which itself reinforces the notion that I may be asleep!

    Suppose then that I am dreaming—it isn’t true that I,
    with my eyes open, am moving my head and stretching out
    my hands. Suppose, indeed that I don’t even have hands or
    any body at all. Still, it has to be admitted that the visions
    that come in sleep are like paintings: they must have been
    made as copies of real things; so at least these general kinds
    of things— eyes, head, hands and the body as a whole—must
    be real and not imaginary. For even when painters try to
    depict sirens and satyrs with the most extraordinary bodies,
    they simply jumble up the limbs of different kinds of real
    animals, rather than inventing natures that are entirely
    new. If they do succeed in thinking up something completely
    fictitious and unreal—not remotely like anything ever seen
    before—at least the colours used in the picture must be real.
    Similarly, although these general kinds of things— eyes,
    head, hands and so on—could be imaginary, there is no
    denying that certain even simpler and more universal kinds
    of things are real. These are the elements out of which we
    make all our mental images of things—the true and also the
    false ones.

    These simpler and more universal kinds include body,
    and extension; the shape of extended things; their quantity,
    size and number; the places things can be in, the time
    through which they can last, and so on.

    So it seems reasonable to conclude that physics, astron-
    omy, medicine, and all other sciences dealing with things
    that have complex structures are doubtful; while arithmetic,
    geometry and other studies of the simplest and most general

    things—whether they really exist in nature or not—contain
    something certain and indubitable. For whether I am awake
    or asleep, two plus three makes five, and a square has only
    four sides. It seems impossible to suspect that such obvious
    truths might be false.

    However, I have for many years been sure that there is
    an all-powerful God who made me to be the sort of creature
    that I am. How do I know that he hasn’t brought it about
    that there is no earth, no sky, nothing that takes up space,
    no shape, no size, no place, while making sure that all these
    things appear to me to exist? Anyway, I sometimes think
    that others go wrong even when they think they have the
    most perfect knowledge; so how do I know that I myself don’t
    go wrong every time I add two and three or count the sides
    of a square? Well, ·you might say·, God would not let me
    be deceived like that, because he is said to be supremely
    good. But, ·I reply·, if God’s goodness would stop him from
    letting me be deceived •all the time, you would expect it to
    stop him from allowing me to be deceived even •occasionally;
    yet clearly I sometimes am deceived.

    Some people would deny the existence of such a powerful
    God rather than believe that everything else is uncertain.
    Let us grant them—for purposes of argument—that there
    is no God, and theology is fiction. On their view, then, I
    am a product of fate or chance or a long chain of causes
    and effects. But the less powerful they make my original
    cause, the more likely it is that I am so imperfect as to be
    deceived all the time—because deception and error seem to
    be imperfections. Having no answer to these arguments, I
    am driven back to the position that doubts can properly be
    raised about any of my former beliefs. I don’t reach this
    conclusion in a flippant or casual manner, but on the basis
    of powerful and well thought-out reasons. So in future, if I
    want to discover any certainty, I must withhold my assent

    2

    Meditations René Descartes Second Meditation

    from these former beliefs just as carefully as I withhold it
    from obvious falsehoods.

    It isn’t enough merely to have noticed this, though; I must
    make an effort to remember it. My old familiar opinions
    keep coming back, and against my will they capture my
    belief. It is as though they had a right to a place in my
    belief-system as a result of long occupation and the law of
    custom. These habitual opinions of mine are indeed highly
    probable; although they are in a sense doubtful, as I have
    shown, it is more reasonable to believe than to deny them.
    But if I go on viewing them in that light I shall never get out
    of the habit of confidently assenting to them. To conquer
    that habit, therefore, I had better switch right around and
    pretend (for a while) that these former opinions of mine are
    utterly false and imaginary. I shall do this until I have
    something to counter-balance the weight of old opinion,
    and the distorting influence of habit no longer prevents me
    from judging correctly. However far I go in my distrustful
    attitude, no actual harm will come of it, because my project
    won’t affect how I •act, but only how I •go about acquiring
    knowledge.

    So I shall suppose that some malicious, powerful, cun-

    ning demon has done all he can to deceive me—rather than
    this being done by God, who is supremely good and the
    source of truth. I shall think that the sky, the air, the
    earth, colours, shapes, sounds and all external things are
    merely dreams that the demon has contrived as traps for my
    judgment. I shall consider myself as having no hands or eyes,
    or flesh, or blood or senses, but as having falsely believed
    that I had all these things. I shall stubbornly persist in this
    train of thought; and even if I can’t learn any truth, I shall at
    least do what I can do, which is to be on my guard against
    accepting any falsehoods, so that the deceiver—however
    powerful and cunning he may be—will be unable to affect me
    in the slightest. This will be hard work, though, and a kind
    of laziness pulls me back into my old ways. Like a prisoner
    who dreams that he is free, starts to suspect that it is merely
    a dream, and wants to go on dreaming rather than waking
    up, so I am content to slide back into my old opinions; I
    fear being shaken out of them because I am afraid that my
    peaceful sleep may be followed by hard labour when I wake,
    and that I shall have to struggle not in the light but in the
    imprisoning darkness of the problems I have raised.

    Second Meditation:
    The nature of the human mind, and how it is better known than the body

    Yesterday’s meditation raised doubts—ones that are too
    serious to be ignored—which I can see no way of resolving.
    I feel like someone who is suddenly dropped into a deep

    whirlpool that tumbles him around so that he can neither
    stand on the bottom nor swim to the top. However, I shall
    force my way up, and try once more to carry out the project

    3

    Meditations René Descartes Second Meditation

    that I started on yesterday. I will set aside anything that
    admits of the slightest doubt, treating it as though I had
    found it to be outright false; and I will carry on like that until
    I find something certain, or—at worst—until I become certain
    that there is no certainty. Archimedes said that if he had
    one firm and immovable point he could lift the world ·with
    a long enough lever·; so I too can hope for great things if I
    manage to find just one little thing that is solid and certain.

    I will suppose, then, that everything I see is fictitious. I
    will believe that my memory tells me nothing but lies. I have
    no senses. Body, shape, extension, movement and place are
    illusions. So what remains true? Perhaps just the one fact
    that nothing is certain!

    [This paragraph is presented as a further to-and-fro argument be-
    tween two people. Remember that this isn’t how Descartes wrote it.]

    Hopeful: Still, how do I know that there isn’t something—
    not on that list—about which there is no room for even the
    slightest doubt? Isn’t there a God (call him what you will)
    who gives me the thoughts I am now having?

    Doubtful: But why do I think this, since I might myself
    be the author of these thoughts?

    Hopeful: But then doesn’t it follow that I am, at least,
    something?

    Doubtful: This is very confusing, because I have just said
    that I have no senses and no body, and I am so bound up
    with a body and with senses that one would think that I can’t
    exist without them. Now that I have convinced myself that
    there is nothing in the world—no sky, no earth, no minds,
    no bodies—does it follow that I don’t exist either?

    Hopeful: No it does not follow; for if I convinced myself
    of something then I certainly existed.

    Doubtful: But there is a supremely powerful and cunning
    deceiver who deliberately deceives me all the time!

    Hopeful: Even then, if he is deceiving me I undoubtedly

    exist: let him deceive me all he can, he will never bring it
    about that I am nothing while I think I am something. So
    after thoroughly thinking the matter through I conclude that
    this proposition, I am, I exist, must be true whenever I assert
    it or think it.

    But this ‘I’ that must exist—I still don’t properly under-
    stand what it is; so I am at risk of confusing it with something
    else, thereby falling into error in the very item of knowledge
    that I maintain is the most certain and obvious of all. To get
    straight about what this ‘I’ is, I shall go back and think some
    more about what I believed myself to be before I started this
    meditation. I will eliminate from those beliefs anything that
    could be even slightly called into question by the arguments I
    have been using, which will leave me with only beliefs about
    myself that are certain and unshakable.

    Well, then, what did I think I was? A man. But what is a
    man? Shall I say ‘a rational animal’? No; for then I should
    have to ask what an animal is, and what rationality is—each
    question would lead me on to other still harder ones, and this
    would take more time than I can spare. Let me focus instead
    on the beliefs that spontaneously and naturally came to me
    whenever I thought about what I was. The first such belief
    was that I had a face, hands, arms and the whole structure
    of bodily parts that corpses also have—I call it the body. The
    next belief was that I ate and drank, that I moved about,
    and that I engaged in sense-perception and thinking; these
    things, I thought, were done by the soul. [In this work ‘the soul’
    = ‘the mind’; it has no religious implications.] If I gave any thought
    to what this soul was like, I imagined it to be something
    thin and filmy— like a wind or fire or ether—permeating my
    more solid parts. I was more sure about the body, though,
    thinking that I knew exactly what sort of thing it was. If
    I had tried to put my conception of the body into words, I
    would have said this:

    4

    Meditations René Descartes Second Meditation

    By a ‘body’ I understand whatever has a definite shape
    and position, and can occupy a ·region of· space in
    such a way as to keep every other body out of it; it can
    be perceived by touch, sight, hearing, taste or smell,
    and can be moved in various ways.

    I would have added that a body can’t start up movements
    by itself, and can move only through being moved by other
    things that bump into it. It seemed to me quite out of
    character for a body to be able to •initiate movements, or
    to able to •sense and think, and I was amazed that certain
    bodies—·namely, human ones·—could do those things.

    But now that I am supposing there is a supremely pow-
    erful and malicious deceiver who has set out to trick me in
    every way he can—now what shall I say that I am? Can I
    now claim to have any of the features that I used to think
    belong to a body? When I think about them really carefully,
    I find that they are all open to doubt: I shan’t waste time
    by showing this about each of them separately. Now, what
    about the features that I attributed to the soul? Nutrition or
    movement? Since now ·I am pretending that· I don’t have a
    body, these are mere fictions. Sense-perception? One needs
    a body in order to perceive; and, besides, when dreaming I
    have seemed to perceive through the senses many things that
    I later realized I had not perceived in that way. Thinking? At
    last I have discovered it—thought! This is the one thing that
    can’t be separated from me. I am, I exist—that is certain.
    But for how long? For as long as I am thinking. But perhaps
    no longer than that; for it might be that if I stopped thinking
    I would stop existing; and ·I have to treat that possibility as
    though it were actual, because· my present policy is to reject
    everything that isn’t necessarily true. Strictly speaking, then,
    I am simply a thing that thinks—a mind, or soul, or intellect,
    or reason, these being words whose meaning I have only just
    come to know. Still, I am a real, existing thing. What kind of

    a thing? I have answered that: a thinking thing.
    What else am I? I will use my imagination to see if I am

    anything more. I am not that structure of limbs and organs
    that is called a human body; nor am I a thin vapour that
    permeates the limbs—a wind, fire, air, breath, or whatever I
    imagine; for I have supposed all these things to be nothing
    ·because I have supposed all bodies to be nothing·. Even if
    I go on supposing them to be nothing, I am still something.
    But these things that I suppose to be nothing because they
    are unknown to me—might they not in fact be identical with
    the I of which I am aware? I don’t know; and just now I
    shan’t discuss the matter, because I can form opinions only
    about things that I know. I know that I exist, and I am
    asking: what is this I that I know? My knowledge of it can’t
    depend on things of whose existence I am still unaware; so
    it can’t depend on anything that I invent in my imagination.
    The word ‘invent’ points to what is wrong with relying on
    my imagination in this matter: if I used imagination to show
    that I was something or other, that would be mere invention,
    mere story-telling; for imagining is simply contemplating
    the shape or image of a bodily thing. [Descartes here relies
    on a theory of his about the psychology of imagination.] That makes
    imagination suspect, for while I know for sure that I exist, I
    know that everything relating to the nature of body ·including
    imagination· could be mere dreams; so it would be silly
    for me to say ‘I will use my imagination to get a clearer
    understanding of what I am’—as silly, indeed, as to say ‘I
    am now awake, and see some truth; but I shall deliberately
    fall asleep so as to see even more, and more truly, in my
    dreams’! If my mind is to get a clear understanding of its
    own nature, it had better not look to the imagination for it.

    Well, then, what am I? A thing that thinks. What is that?
    A thing that doubts, understands, affirms, denies, wants,
    refuses, and also imagines and senses.

    5

    Meditations René Descartes Second Meditation

    That is a long list of attributes for me to have—and it
    really is I who have them all. Why should it not be? Isn’t it
    one and the same ‘I’ who now

    doubts almost everything,
    understands some things,
    affirms this one thing—·namely, that I exist and think·,
    denies everything else,
    wants to know more,
    refuses to be deceived,
    imagines many things involuntarily, and
    is aware of others that seem to come from the senses?

    Isn’t all this just as true as the fact that I exist, even if I am
    in a perpetual dream, and even if my creator is doing his best
    to deceive me? Which of all these activities is distinct from
    my thinking? Which of them can be said to be separate from
    myself? The fact that it is I who doubt and understand and
    want is so obvious that I can’t see how to make it any clearer.
    But the ‘I’ who imagines is also this same ‘I’. For even if (as I
    am pretending) none of the things that I imagine really exist,
    I really do imagine them, and this is part of my thinking.
    Lastly, it is also this same ‘I’ who senses, or is aware of
    bodily things seemingly through the senses. Because I may
    be dreaming, I can’t say for sure that I now see the flames,
    hear the wood crackling, and feel the heat of the fire; but
    I certainly seem to see, to hear, and to be warmed. This
    cannot be false; what is called ‘sensing’ is strictly just this
    seeming, and when ‘sensing’ is understood in this restricted
    sense of the word it too is simply thinking.

    All this is starting to give me a better understanding
    of what I am. But I still can’t help thinking that bodies—
    of which I form mental images and which the senses
    investigate—are much more clearly known to me than is
    this puzzling ‘I’ that can’t be pictured in the imagination.
    It would be surprising if this were right, though; for it

    would be surprising if I had a clearer grasp of things that I
    realize are doubtful, unknown and foreign to me—·namely,
    bodies·—than I have of what is true and known— namely
    my own self. But I see what the trouble is: I keep drifting
    towards that error because my mind likes to wander freely,
    refusing to respect the boundaries that truth lays down. Very
    well, then; I shall let it run free for a while, so that when
    the time comes to rein it in it won’t be so resistant to being
    pulled back.

    Let us consider the things that people ordinarily think
    they understand best of all, namely the bodies that we touch
    and see. I don’t mean bodies in general—for our general
    thoughts are apt to be confused—but one particular body:
    this piece of wax, for example. It has just been taken from
    the honeycomb; it still tastes of honey and has the scent of
    the flowers from which the honey was gathered; its colour,
    shape and size are plain to see; it is hard, cold and can be
    handled easily; if you rap it with your knuckle it makes a
    sound. In short, it has everything that seems to be needed
    for a body to be known perfectly clearly. But as I speak these
    words I hold the wax near to the fire, and look! The taste and
    smell vanish, the colour changes, the shape is lost, the size
    increases; the wax becomes liquid and hot; you can hardly
    touch it, and it no longer makes a sound when you strike it.
    But is it still the same wax? Of course it is; no-one denies
    this. So what was it about the wax that I understood so
    clearly? Evidently it was not any of the features that the
    senses told me of; for all of them— brought to me through
    taste, smell, sight, touch or hearing—have now altered, yet
    it is still the same wax.

    Perhaps what I now think about the wax indicates what
    its nature was all along. If that is right, then the wax was
    not the sweetness of the honey, the scent of the flowers, the
    whiteness, the shape, or the sound, but was rather a body

    6

    Meditations René Descartes Second Meditation

    that recently presented itself to me in those ways but now
    appears differently. But what exactly is this thing that I
    am now imagining? Well, if we take away whatever doesn’t
    belong to the wax (·that is, everything that the wax could be
    without·), what is left is merely something extended, flexible
    and changeable. What do ‘flexible’ and ‘changeable’ mean
    here? I can imaginatively picture this piece of wax changing
    from round to square, from square to triangular, and so
    on. But that isn’t what changeability is. In knowing that
    the wax is changeable I understand that it can go through
    endlessly many changes of that kind, far more than I can
    depict in my imagination; so it isn’t my imagination that
    gives me my grasp of the wax as flexible and changeable.
    Also, what does ‘extended’ mean? Is the wax’s extension
    also unknown? It increases if the wax melts, and increases
    again if it boils; the wax can be extended in many more ways
    (·that is, with many more shapes·) than I will ever bring
    before my imagination. I am forced to conclude that the
    nature of this piece of wax isn’t revealed by my imagination,
    but is perceived by the mind alone. (I am speaking of •this
    particular piece of wax; the point is even clearer with regard
    to •wax in general.) This wax that is perceived by the mind
    alone is, of course, the same wax that I see, touch, and
    picture in my imagination—in short the same wax I thought
    it to be from the start. But although my perception of it
    seemed to be a case of vision and touch and imagination, it
    isn’t so and it never was. Rather, it is purely a scrutiny by
    the mind alone— formerly an imperfect and confused one,
    but now vivid and clear because I am now concentrating
    carefully on what the wax consists in.

    As I reach this conclusion I am amazed at how prone to
    error my mind is. For although I am thinking all this out
    within myself, silently, I do it with the help of words, and
    I am at risk of being led astray by them. When the wax is

    in front of us, we say that we see it, not that we judge it to
    be there from its colour or shape; and this might make me
    think that knowledge of the wax comes from what the eye
    sees rather than from the perception of the mind alone. But
    ·this is clearly wrong, as the following example shows·. If I
    look out of the window and see men crossing the square, as
    I have just done, I say that I see the men themselves, just
    as I say that I see the wax; yet do I see any more than hats
    and coats that could conceal robots? I judge that they are
    men. Something that I thought I saw with my eyes, therefore,
    was really grasped solely by my mind’s faculty of judgment
    [= ‘ability or capacity to make judgments’].

    However, someone who wants to know more than the
    common crowd should be ashamed to base his doubts on
    ordinary ways of talking. Let us push ahead, then, and
    ask: When was my perception of the wax’s nature more
    perfect and clear? Was it •when I first looked at the wax, and
    thought I knew it through my senses? Or is it •now, after I
    have enquired more carefully into the wax’s nature and into
    how it is known? It would be absurd to hesitate in answering
    the question; for what clarity and sharpness was there in
    my earlier perception of the wax? Was there anything in it
    that •a lower animal couldn’t have? But when I consider the
    wax apart from its outward forms—take its clothes off, so to
    speak, and consider it naked—then although my judgment
    may still contain errors, at least I am now having a perception
    of a sort that requires •a human mind.

    But what am I to say about this mind, or about myself?
    (So far, remember, I don’t admit that there is anything to me
    except a mind.) What, I ask, is this ‘I’ that seems to perceive
    the wax so clearly? Surely, I am aware of •my own self in a
    truer and more certain way than I am of •the wax, and also
    in a much more distinct and evident way. What leads me to
    think that •the wax exists—namely, that I see it— leads much

    7

    Meditations René Descartes Second Meditation

    more obviously to the conclusion that •I exist. What I see
    might not really be the wax; perhaps I don’t even have eyes
    with which to see anything. But when I see or think I see (I
    am not here distinguishing the two), it is simply not possible
    that I who am now thinking am not something. Similarly,
    that •I exist follows from the other bases for judging that
    •the wax exists – that I touch it, that I imagine it, or any
    other basis—and similarly for my bases for judging that
    anything else exists outside me. As I came to perceive the
    wax more distinctly by applying not just sight and touch but
    other considerations, all this too contributed to my knowing
    myself even more distinctly, because whatever goes into my
    perception of •the wax or of any other body must do even
    more to establish the nature of •my own mind. What comes
    to my mind from bodies, therefore, helps me to know my

    mind distinctly; yet all of that pales into insignificance—it
    is hardly worth mentioning—when compared with what
    my mind contains within itself that enables me to know
    it distinctly.

    See! With no effort I have reached the place where I
    wanted to be! I now know that even bodies are perceived not
    by the senses or by imagination but by the intellect alone,
    not through their being touched or seen but through their
    being understood; and this helps me to know plainly that
    I can perceive my own mind more easily and clearly than I
    can anything else. Since the grip of old opinions is hard to
    shake off, however, I want to pause and meditate for a while
    on this new knowledge of mine, fixing it more deeply in my
    memory.

    8

      First Meditation
      Second Meditation

    Meditations on First Philosophy
    in which are demonstrated the existence of God and the distinction between

    the human soul and body

    René Descartes

    Copyright ©

    20

    10

    –20

    15

    All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett

    [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as
    though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations,
    are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . . . . indicates
    the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth.—In his title for this work,
    Descartes is following a tradition (started by Aristotle) which uses ‘first philosophy’ as a label for metaphysics.

    First launched: July 2004 Last amended: April 2007

    Contents

    First Meditation 1

    Second Meditation 3

  • Third Meditation
  • 9

  • Fourth Meditation
  • 17

    Fifth Meditation 23

    Sixth Meditation 27

    Meditations René Descartes Third Meditation

    Third Meditation:
    God

    [Before we move on, a translation matter should be confronted. It con-
    cerns the Latin adjectives

    clarus and distinctus
    the corresponding French adjectives

    clair and distinct
    and the corresponding English adjectives

    ‘vivid’ and ‘clear’.
    Every other translator of this work into English has put

    ‘clear’ and ‘distinct’

    and for a while the present translator in cowardly fashion followed suit.

    But the usual translation is simply wrong, and we ought to free ourselves

    from it. The crucial point concerns clarus (and everything said about that

    here is equally true of the French clair). The word can mean ‘clear’ in our

    sense, and when Descartes uses it outside the clarus et distinctus phrase,
    it seems usually to be in that sense. But in that phrase he uses clarus
    in its other meaning—its more common meaning in Latin—of ‘bright’ or

    ‘vivid’ or the like, as in clara lux = ‘broad daylight’. If in the phrase clarus

    et distinctus Descartes meant clarus in its lesser meaning of ‘clear’, then

    what is there left for ‘distinctus’ to mean? Descartes doesn’t explain

    these terms here, but in his Principles of Philosophy 1:45–6 he does

    so—in a manner that completely condemns the usual translation. He

    writes: ‘I call a perception claram when it is present and accessible to

    the attentive mind—just as we say that we see something clare when

    it is present to the eye’s gaze and stimulates it with a sufficient degree

    of strength and accessibility. I call a perception distinctam if, as well

    as being clara, it is so sharply separated from all other perceptions that

    every part of it is clarum.. . . . The example of pain shows that a perception

    can be clara without being distincta but not vice versa. When for example

    someone feels an intense pain, his perception of it is clarissima, but it

    isn’t always clear, because people often get this perception muddled with

    an obscure judgment they make about something that they think exists

    in the painful spot. . . .’ and so on. Of course he is not saying anything

    as stupid as that intense pain is always clear! His point is that pain is

    vivid, up-front, not shady or obscure. And for an idea to be distincta is

    for every nook and cranny of it to be vivid; which is not a bad way of

    saying that it is in our sense ‘clear’.]
    I will now shut my eyes, block my ears, cut off all my

    senses. I will regard all my mental images of bodily things
    as empty, false and worthless (if I could, I would clear them
    out of my mind altogether). I will get into conversation with
    myself, examine myself more deeply, and try in this way
    gradually to know myself more intimately. I am a thing
    that thinks, i.e that doubts, affirms, denies, understands
    some things, is ignorant of many others, wills, and refuses.
    This thing also imagines and has sensory perceptions; for,
    as I remarked before, even if the objects of my sensory
    experience and imagination don’t exist outside me, still
    sensory perception and imagination themselves, considered
    simply as mental events, certainly do occur in me.

    That lists everything that I truly know, or at least every-
    thing I have, up to now, discovered that I know. Now I will
    look more carefully to see whether I have overlooked other
    facts about myself. I am certain that I am a thinking thing.
    Doesn’t that tell me what it takes for me to be certain about
    anything? In this first item of knowledge there is simply
    a vivid and clear perception of what I am asserting; this
    wouldn’t be enough to make me certain of its truth if it could
    ever turn out that something that I perceived so vividly and
    clearly was false. So I now seem to be able to lay it down as a
    general rule that whatever I perceive very vividly and clearly
    is true.

    9

    Meditations René Descartes Third Meditation

    I previously accepted as perfectly certain and evident
    many things that I afterwards realized were doubtful—the
    earth, sky, stars, and everything else that I took in through
    the senses—but in those cases what I perceived clearly were
    merely the ideas or thoughts of those things that came into
    my mind; and I am still not denying that those ideas occur
    within me. But I used also to believe that my ideas came from
    things outside that resembled them in all respects. Indeed, I
    believed this for so long that I wrongly came to think that I
    perceived it clearly. In fact, it was false; or anyway if it was
    true it was not thanks to the strength of my perceptions.

    But what about when I was considering something simple
    and straightforward in arithmetic or geometry, for example
    that two plus three makes five? Didn’t I see these things
    clearly enough to accept them as true? Indeed, the only
    reason I could find for doubting them was this: Perhaps
    some God could have made me so as to be deceived even in
    those matters that seemed most obvious. Whenever I bring
    to mind my old belief in the supreme power of God, I have
    to admit that God could, if he wanted to, easily make me go
    wrong even about things that I think I see perfectly clearly.
    But when I turn my thought onto the things themselves—the
    ones I think I perceive clearly—I find them so convincing that
    I spontaneously exclaim: ‘Let him do his best to deceive me!
    He will never bring it about that I am nothing while I think I
    am something; or make it true in the future that I have never
    existed, given that I do now exist; or bring it about that two
    plus three make more or less than five, or anything else like
    this in which I see a plain contradiction.’ Also, since I have
    no evidence that there is a deceiving God, and don’t even
    know for sure that there is a God at all, the reason for doubt
    that depends purely on this supposition of a deceiving God
    is a very slight and theoretical one. However, I shall want to
    remove even this slight reason for doubt; so when I get the

    opportunity I shall examine whether there is a God, and (if
    there is) whether he can be a deceiver. If I don’t settle this, it
    seems, then I can never be quite certain about anything else.

    First, if I am to proceed in an orderly way I should classify
    my thoughts into definite kinds, and ask which kinds can
    properly be said to be true or false. Some of my thoughts are,
    so to speak, images or pictures of things—as when I think of
    a man, or a chimera, or the sky, or an angel, or God— and
    strictly speaking these are the only thoughts that should be
    called ‘ideas’. Other thoughts have more to them than that:
    for example when I will, or am afraid, or affirm, or deny, my
    thought represents some particular thing but it also includes
    something more than merely the likeness of that thing. Some
    thoughts in this category are called volitions or emotions,
    while others are called judgments.

    When ideas are considered solely in themselves and not
    taken to be connected to anything else, they can’t be false;
    for whether it is •a goat that I am imagining or •a chimera,
    either way it is true that I do imagine it. Nor is there falsity
    in the will or the emotions; for even if the things I want are
    wicked or non-existent, it is still true that I want them. All
    that is left—the only kind of thought where I must watch out
    for mistakes—are judgments. And the mistake they most
    commonly involve is to judge that my ideas resemble things
    outside me. Of course, if I considered the ideas themselves
    simply as aspects of my thought and not as connected to
    anything else, they could hardly lead me into any error.

    Among my ideas, some seem to be •innate, some to be
    •caused from the outside, and others to have been •invented
    by me. As I see it, •my understanding of what a thing is,
    what truth is, and what thought is, derives purely from my
    own nature, ·which means that it is innate·; •my hearing a
    noise or seeing the sun or feeling the fire comes from things
    outside me; and •sirens, hippogriffs and the like are my own

    10

    Meditations René Descartes Third Meditation

    invention. But perhaps really all my ideas are caused from
    the outside, or all are innate, or all are made up; for I still
    have not clearly perceived their true origin.

    But my main question now concerns the ideas that I
    take to come from things outside me: why do I think they
    resemble these things? Nature has apparently taught me
    to think that they do. But also I know from experience that
    these ideas don’t depend on my will, and thus don’t depend
    simply on me. They often come into my mind without my
    willing them to: right now, for example, I have a feeling of
    warmth, whether I want to or not, and that leads me to think
    that this sensation or idea of heat comes from something
    other than myself, namely the heat of a fire by which I am
    sitting. And it seems natural to suppose that what comes to
    me from that external thing will be like it rather than unlike
    it.

    Now let me see if these arguments are strong enough.
    When I say ‘Nature taught me to think this’, all I mean is
    that •I have a spontaneous impulse to believe it, not that
    •I am shown its truth by some natural light. There is a
    great difference between those. Things that are revealed by
    the natural light—for example, that if I am doubting then I
    exist—are not open to any doubt, because no other faculty
    that might show them to be false could be as trustworthy
    as the natural light. My natural impulses, however, have
    no such privilege: I have often come to think that they had
    pushed me the wrong way on moral questions, and I don’t
    see any reason to trust them in other things.

    Then again, although these ideas don’t depend on my will,
    it doesn’t follow that they must come from things located
    outside me. Perhaps they come from some faculty of mine
    other than my will—one that I don’t fully know about—which
    produces these ideas without help from external things;
    this is, after all, just how I have always thought ideas are

    produced in me when I am dreaming. Similarly, the natural
    impulses that I have been talking about, though they seem
    opposed to my will, come from within me; ·which provides
    evidence that I can cause things that my will does not cause·.

    Finally, even if these ideas do come from things other
    than myself, it doesn’t follow that they must resemble those
    things. Indeed, I think I have often discovered objects to be
    very unlike my ideas of them. For example, I find within
    me two different ideas of the sun: •one seems to come from
    the senses—it is a prime example of an idea that I reckon to
    have an external source—and it makes the sun appear very
    small; •the other is based on astronomical reasoning—i.e.
    it is based on notions that are innate in me (or else it is
    constructed by me in some other way)—and it shows the
    sun to be many times larger than the earth. Obviously these
    ideas cannot both resemble the external sun; and reason
    convinces me that the idea that seems to have come most
    directly from the sun itself in fact does not resemble it at all.

    These considerations show that it isn’t reliable judgment
    but merely some blind impulse that has led me to think that
    there exist outside me things that give ideas or images [=
    ‘likenesses’] of themselves through the sense organs or in some
    other way.

    Perhaps, though, there is another way of investigating
    whether some of the things of which I have ideas really
    do exist outside me. Considered simply as mental events,
    my ideas seem to be all on a par: they all appear to come
    from inside me in the same way. But considered as images
    representing things other than themselves, it is clear that
    they differ widely. Undoubtedly, the •ideas that represent
    substances amount to something more—they contain within
    themselves more representative reality—than do the •ideas
    that merely represent modes [= ‘qualities’]. Again, the •idea
    that gives me my understanding of a supreme God—eternal,

    11

    Meditations René Descartes Third Meditation

    infinite, unchangeable, omniscient, omnipotent and the
    creator of everything that exists except for himself—certainly
    has in it more representative reality than the •ideas that
    represent merely finite substances.

    Now it is obvious by the natural light that the total cause
    of something must contain at least as much reality as does
    the effect. For where could the effect get its reality from if
    not from the cause? And how could the cause give reality to
    the effect unless it first had that reality itself? Two things
    follow from this: that something can’t arise from nothing,
    and that what is more perfect—that is, contains in itself
    more reality—can’t arise from what is less perfect. And this
    is plainly true not only for ‘actual’ or ‘intrinsic’ reality (as
    philosophers call it) but also for the representative reality of
    ideas—that is, the reality that a idea represents. A stone,
    for example, can begin to exist only if it is produced by
    something that contains—either straightforwardly or in some
    higher form—everything that is to be found in the stone;
    similarly, heat can’t be produced in a previously cold object
    except by something of at least the same order of perfection
    as heat, and so on. (·I don’t say simply ‘except by something
    that is hot’, because that is not necessary. The thing
    could be caused to be hot by something that doesn’t itself
    straightforwardly contain heat—i.e. that isn’t itself hot— but
    contains heat in a higher form, that is, something of a higher
    order of perfection than heat. Thus, for example, although
    God is obviously not himself hot, he can cause something to
    be hot because he contains heat not straightforwardly but in
    a higher form·.) But it is also true that the idea of heat or of
    a stone can be caused in me only by something that contains
    at least as much reality as I conceive to be in the heat or
    in the stone. For although this cause does not transfer any
    of its actual or intrinsic reality to my idea, it still can’t be
    less real. An idea need have no intrinsic reality except what

    it derives from my thought, of which it is a mode. But any
    idea that has representative reality must surely come from
    a cause that contains at least as much intrinsic reality as
    there is representative reality in the idea. For if we suppose
    that an idea contains something that was not in its cause, it
    must have got this from nothing; yet the kind of reality that
    is involved in something’s being represented in the mind by
    an idea, though it may not be very perfect, certainly isn’t
    nothing, and so it can’t come from nothing.

    It might be thought that since the reality that I am
    considering in my ideas is merely representative, it might
    be possessed by its cause only representatively and not
    intrinsically. ·That would mean that the cause is itself
    an idea, because only ideas have representative reality·.
    But that would be wrong. Although one idea may perhaps
    originate from another, there can’t be an infinite regress
    of such ideas; eventually one must come back to an idea
    whose cause isn’t an idea, and this cause must be a kind
    of archetype [= ‘pattern or model, from which copies are made’] con-
    taining intrinsically all the reality or perfection that the idea
    contains only representatively. So the natural light makes it
    clear to me that my ideas are like pictures or images that can
    easily •fall short of the perfection of the things from which
    they are taken, but which can’t •exceed it.

    The longer and more carefully I examine all these points,
    the more vividly and clearly I recognize their truth. But what
    is my conclusion to be? If I find that

    •some idea of mine has so much representative reality
    that I am sure the same reality doesn’t reside in me,
    either straightforwardly or in a higher form, and hence
    that I myself can’t be the cause of the idea,

    then, ·because everything must have some cause·, it will
    necessarily follow that

    12

    Meditations René Descartes Third Meditation

    •I am not alone in the world: there exists some other
    thing that is the cause of that idea.

    If no such idea is to be found in me, I shall have no argument
    to show that anything exists apart from myself; for, despite
    a most careful and wide-ranging survey, this is the only
    argument I have so far been able to find.

    Among my ideas, apart from the one that gives me a
    representation of myself, which can’t present any difficulty
    in this context, there are ideas that variously represent God,
    inanimate bodies, angels, animals and finally other men like
    myself.

    As regards my ideas of other men, or animals, or angels,
    I can easily understand that they could be put together from
    the ideas I have of myself, of bodies and of God, even if the
    world contained no men besides me, no animals and no
    angels.

    As to my ideas of bodies, so far as I can see they contain
    nothing that is so great or excellent that it couldn’t have
    originated in myself. For if I examine them thoroughly, one
    by one, as I did the idea of the wax yesterday, I realize that
    the following short list gives everything that I perceive vividly
    and clearly in them:

    •size, or extension in length, breadth and depth;
    •shape, which is a function of the boundaries of this
    extension;

    •position, which is a relation between various items
    possessing shape;

    • motion, or change in position.
    To these may be added

    •substance, duration and number.
    But as for all the rest, including light and colours, sounds,
    smells, tastes, heat and cold and the other qualities that can
    be known by touch, I think of these in such a confused and

    obscure way that I don’t even know whether they are true
    or false, that is, whether my ideas of them are ideas of real
    things or of non-things. Strictly speaking, only judgments
    can be true or false; but we can also speak of an idea as
    ‘false’ in a certain sense—we call it ‘materially false’—if it
    represents a non-thing as a thing. For example, my ideas of
    heat and cold have so little clarity and distinctness that they
    don’t enable me to know whether

    •cold is merely the absence of heat, or
    •heat is merely the absence of cold, or
    •heat and cold are both real ·positive· qualities, or
    •neither heat nor cold is a real ·positive· quality.

    If the right answer is that cold is nothing but the absence of
    heat, the idea that represents it to me as something real and
    positive deserves to be called ‘false’; and the same goes for
    other ideas of this kind.

    Such ideas obviously don’t have to be caused by some-
    thing other than myself. •If they are false—that is, if they
    represent non-things—then they are in me only because of
    a deficiency or lack of perfection in my nature, which is to
    say that they arise from nothing; I know this by the natural
    light. •If on the other hand they are true, there is no reason
    why they shouldn’t arise from myself, since they represent
    such a slight reality that I can’t even distinguish it from a
    non-thing.

    With regard to the vivid and clear elements in my ideas of
    bodies, it appears that I could have borrowed some of these
    from my idea of myself, namely substance, duration, number
    and anything else of this kind. For example, I think that a
    stone is a substance, or is a thing capable of existing indepen-
    dently, and I also think that I am a substance. Admittedly I
    conceive of myself as a thing that thinks and isn’t extended,
    and of the stone as a thing that is extended and doesn’t
    think, so that the two conceptions differ enormously; but

    13

    Meditations René Descartes Third Meditation

    they seem to have the classification ‘substance’ in common.
    Again, I perceive that I now exist, and remember that I have
    existed •for some time; moreover, I have various thoughts
    that I can •count; it is in these ways that I acquire the ideas
    of •duration and •number that I can then transfer to other
    things. As for all the other elements that make up the ideas
    of bodies— extension, shape, position and movement—these
    are not straightforwardly contained in me, since I am nothing
    but a thinking thing; but since they are merely modes of
    a substance, and I am a substance, it seems possible that
    they are contained in me in some higher form. ·That is, I
    am not myself extended, shaped etc., but because I am a
    substance I am (so to speak) metaphysically one up on these
    mere modes, which implies that I can contain within me
    whatever it takes to cause the ideas of them·.

    So there remains only the idea of God: is there any-
    thing in that which couldn’t have originated in myself? By
    the word ‘God’ I understand a substance that is infinite,
    eternal, unchangeable, independent, supremely intelligent,
    supremely powerful, which created myself and anything else
    that may exist. The more carefully I concentrate on these
    attributes, the less possible it seems that any of them could
    have originated from me alone. So this whole discussion
    implies that God necessarily exists.

    It is true that my being a substance explains my having
    the idea of substance; but it does not explain my having the
    idea of an infinite substance. That must come from some
    substance that is itself infinite. I am finite.

    It might be thought that ·this is wrong, because· my
    notion of the •infinite is arrived at merely by negating the
    •finite, just as my conceptions of •rest and •darkness are
    arrived at by negating •movement and •light. ·That would
    be a mistake, however·. I clearly understand that there is
    more reality in an infinite substance than in a finite one,

    and hence that my perception of the infinite, i.e. God, is in
    some way prior to my perception of the finite, i.e. myself.
    Whenever I know that I doubt something or want something,
    I understand that I lack something and am therefore not
    wholly perfect. How could I grasp this unless I had an idea
    of a more perfect being that enabled me to recognize my own
    defects by comparison?

    Nor can it be said that this idea of God could be ‘materially
    false’, and thus have come from nothing, as may be the case
    (I noted this a few moments ago) with the ideas of heat
    and cold. On the contrary, it is utterly vivid and clear, and
    contains in itself more representative reality than any other
    idea; ·that is, it stands for something that is grander, more
    powerful, more real, than any other idea stands for·; so it
    is more true—less open to the suspicion of falsehood—than
    any other idea. This idea of a supremely perfect and infinite
    being is, I say, true in the highest degree; for although one
    might imagine that such a being does not exist, it can’t be
    supposed that the idea of such a being represents something
    unreal in the way that the idea of cold perhaps does. The
    idea is, moreover, utterly vivid and clear. It does not matter
    that I don’t grasp the infinite, or that there are countless
    additional attributes of God that I can’t grasp and perhaps
    can’t even touch in my thought; for it is in the nature of the
    infinite not to be grasped by a finite being like myself. It is
    enough that I understand the infinite, and that I judge that
    all the attributes that I clearly perceive and know to imply
    some perfection—and perhaps countless others of which I
    am ignorant—are present in God either straightforwardly or
    in some higher form. This is enough to make the idea that
    I have of God the truest and most vivid and clear of all my
    ideas.

    ·Here is a possible objection to that line of thought·.
    Perhaps I am greater than I myself understand: perhaps

    14

    Meditations René Descartes Third Meditation

    all the perfections that I attribute to God are ones that I do
    have in some potential form, and they merely haven’t yet
    shown themselves in actuality. My knowledge is gradually
    increasing, and I see no obstacle to its going on increasing to
    infinity. I might then be able to use this increased ·and even-
    tually infinite· knowledge to acquire all the other perfections
    of God. In that case, I already have the potentiality for these
    perfections—why shouldn’t this ·potentiality· be enough to
    enable me to have caused the idea of them ·that is, to have
    caused my idea of God·?

    But all this [that is, the whole of the preceding paragraph] is
    impossible ·for three reasons·. •First, though it is true that
    my knowledge is increasing, and that I have many poten-
    tialities that are not yet actual, this is all quite irrelevant to
    the idea of God, which contains absolutely nothing that is
    potential. Indeed, this gradual increase in knowledge is itself
    the surest sign of imperfection, ·because if I am learning
    more, that shows that there are things I don’t know, and
    that is an imperfection in me·. •What is more, even if my
    knowledge increases for ever, it will never actually be infinite,
    since it will never reach the point where it isn’t capable of a
    further increase; God, on the other hand, I take to be actually
    infinite, so that nothing can be added to his perfection. •And,
    thirdly, strictly speaking potential being is nothing; what it
    takes to cause the representative being of an idea is actual
    being.

    If one concentrates carefully, all this is quite evident by
    the natural light. But when I relax my concentration, and my
    mental vision is blurred by the images of things I perceive
    by the senses, I lose sight of the reasons why my idea of
    more perfect being has to come from a being that really is
    more perfect. So I want to push on with my enquiry, now
    asking a new question: If the more perfect being didn’t exist,
    could I exist? ·My hope is that the answer to this will yield a

    new proof of the existence of a perfect being—a proof that it
    will be easier for me to keep in mind even when I relax my
    concentration·.

    Well, if God didn’t exist, from what would I derive my
    existence? It would have to come from myself, or from my
    parents, or from some other beings less perfect than God
    (a being more perfect than God, or even one as perfect, is
    unthinkable).

    If I had derived my existence from myself, I would not
    now doubt or want or lack anything at all; for I would have
    given myself all the perfections of which I have any idea. So I
    would be God. I mustn’t suppose that the items I lack would
    be harder to get than the ones I now have. On the contrary,
    it would have been far more difficult for me—a thinking
    thing or substance—to emerge out of nothing than merely
    to acquire knowledge of the many things I’m ignorant about,
    because that would merely be giving the substance certain
    accidents. If I had derived my existence from myself—the
    greater achievement—I certainly wouldn’t have denied myself
    the knowledge in question, which is something much easier
    to acquire, or indeed any of the attributes that I perceive to
    be contained in the idea of God; for none of them seem any
    harder to achieve. . . .

    Here is a thought that might seem to undercut that
    argument. Perhaps I have always existed as I do now.
    Then wouldn’t it follow that there need be no cause for my
    existence? No, it does not follow. For a life-span can be
    divided into countless parts, each completely independent
    of the others, so that from my existing at one time it doesn’t
    follow that I exist at later times, unless some cause keeps
    me in existence—one might say that it creates me afresh at
    each moment. Anyone who thinks hard about the nature of
    time will understand that what it takes to •bring a thing into
    existence is also needed to •keep it in existence at each mo-

    15

    Meditations René Descartes Third Meditation

    ment of its duration. So there’s no real distinction between
    •preservation and •creation—only a conceptual one—and this
    is something that the natural light makes evident.

    So I have to ask myself whether I have the power to bring
    it about that I, who now exist, will still exist a minute from
    now. For since I am nothing but a thinking thing—or anyway
    that is the only part of me that I am now concerned with—if
    I had such a power I would undoubtedly be aware of it. But
    I experience no such power, and this shows me quite clearly
    that I depend ·for my continued existence· on some being
    other than myself.

    Perhaps this being is not God, though. Perhaps I was
    produced by causes less perfect than God, such as my
    parents. No; for as I have said before, it is quite clear
    that there must be at least as much reality or perfection
    in the cause as in the effect. And therefore, given that I
    am a thinking thing and have within me some idea of God,
    the cause of me—whatever it is—must itself be a thinking
    thing and must have the idea of all the perfections that I
    attribute to God. What is the cause of this cause of me?
    If it is the cause of its own existence, then it is God; for if
    it has the power of existing through its own strength, then
    undoubtedly it also has the power of actually possessing
    all the perfections of which it has an idea—that is, all the
    perfections that I conceive to be in God. If on the other hand
    it gets its existence from another cause, then the question
    arises all over again regarding this further cause: Does it get
    its existence from itself or from another cause? Eventually
    we must reach the ultimate cause, and this will be God.

    It is clear enough that this sequence of causes of causes
    can’t run back to infinity, especially since I am dealing with
    the cause that not only produced me in the past but also
    preserves me at the present moment.

    One might think this:
    Several partial causes contributed to my creation;
    I received the idea of one of the perfections that I
    attribute to God from one cause, and the idea of
    another from another. Each perfection is to be found
    somewhere in the universe, but no one thing has them
    all.

    That can’t be right, because God’s simplicity—that is, the
    unity or inseparability of all his attributes—is one of the
    most important of the perfections that I understand him
    to have. The idea of his perfections as united in a single
    substance couldn’t have been placed in me by any cause
    that didn’t also provide me with the ideas of the perfections
    themselves; for no cause could have made me understand
    that the perfections are united without at the same time
    showing me what they are.

    Lastly, as regards my parents, even if everything I have
    ever believed about them is true, it is certainly not they
    who keep me in existence. Insofar as I am a thinking thing,
    indeed, they did not even make me; they merely brought
    about an arrangement of matter that I have always regarded
    as containing me (that is, containing my mind, for that is
    all I now take myself to be). So my parents can’t be the
    cause-of-me that I am enquiring about.

    ·Given the failure of every other candidacy for the role
    of cause of me and of my idea of a most perfect being, I
    infer that the only successful candidacy is God’s·. Thus,
    I conclude that the mere fact that I exist and have within
    me an idea of a most perfect being—that is, God—provides a
    clear proof that God does indeed exist.

    It remains for me only to ask how I received this idea from
    God. I didn’t get it from the senses: it has never come to me
    unexpectedly, as do most of the ideas that occur when I seem
    to see and touch and hear things. And it’s not something

    16

    Meditations René Descartes Fourth Meditation

    that I invented, either; for clearly I can’t take anything away
    from it or to add anything to it. ·When an idea is sheerly
    invented, the inventor is free to fiddle with it—add a bit here,
    subtract a bit there—whereas my idea of God is a natural
    unit that doesn’t invite or even permit such interference·.
    The only remaining alternative is that my idea of God is
    innate in me, just as the idea of myself is innate in me.

    It is no surprise that God in creating me should have
    placed this idea in me, to serve as a mark of the craftsman
    stamped on his work. The mark need not be anything distinct
    from the work itself. But the mere fact that God created me
    makes it very believable that I am somehow made in his
    image and likeness, and that I perceive that likeness in the
    same way that I perceive myself. That is, when I turn my
    mind’s eye upon myself, I understand that I am a thing that
    •is incomplete and •dependent on something else, and that
    •aspires without limit to ever greater and better things; but I
    also understand at the same time that he on whom I depend
    has within him all those greater things—not just indefinitely
    but infinitely, not just potentially but actually—and hence

    that he is God. The core of the argument is this: I couldn’t
    exist with the nature that I have—that is, containing within
    me the idea of God—if God didn’t really exist. By ‘God’ I
    mean the very being the idea of whom is within me—the one
    that has no defects and has all those perfections that I can’t
    grasp but can somehow touch with my thought. This shows
    clearly that it is not possible for him to be a deceiver, since
    the natural light makes it clear that all fraud and deception
    depend on some defect.

    But before examining this point more carefully and in-
    vestigating other truths that may be derived from it, I want
    to pause here and spend some time contemplating God;
    to reflect on his attributes and to gaze with wonder and
    adoration on the beauty of this immense light, so far as the
    eye of my darkened intellect can bear it. For just as we
    believe through faith that the supreme happiness of •the
    next life consists in contemplating the divine majesty, so
    experience tells us that this same contemplation, though
    much less perfect, provides the greatest joy we can have in
    •this life.

    Fourth Meditation:
    Truth and falsity

    In these past few days I have become used to keeping
    my mind away from the senses; and I have become strongly
    aware that very little is truly known about bodies, whereas
    much more is known about the human mind and still more
    about God. So now I find it easy to turn my mind away from

    objects of the senses and the imagination, towards objects
    of the intellect alone; these are quite separate from matter,
    ·whereas the objects of sense and imagination are mostly
    made of matter·. Indeed, none of my ideas of corporeal [=
    ‘bodily’] things is as distinct as my idea of the human mind,

    17

    Meditations René Descartes Fourth Meditation

    considered purely as a thinking thing with no size or shape
    or other bodily characteristics. Now, when I consider the fact
    that I have doubts—which means that I am incomplete and
    dependent—that leads to my having a vivid and clear idea of
    a being who is independent and complete, that is, an idea of
    God. And from the mere fact that •I exist and have such an
    idea, I infer that •God exists and that every moment of my
    existence depends on him. This follows clearly; I am sure,
    indeed, that the human intellect can’t know anything that is
    more evident or more certain. And now that I can take into
    account the true God, in whom all the treasures of wisdom
    and knowledge lie hidden, I think I can see a way through to
    knowledge of other things in the universe.

    To begin with, I see that it is impossible that God should
    ever deceive me. Only someone who has something wrong
    with him will engage in trickery or deception. That someone
    is able to deceive others may be a sign of his skill or power,
    but his wanting to deceive them is a sign of his malice or
    weakness; and those are not to be found in God.

    Next, I know from experience that I have a faculty of
    judgment; and this, like everything else I have, was given to
    me by God. Since God doesn’t want to deceive me, I am sure
    that he didn’t give me a faculty of judgment that would lead
    me into error while I was using it correctly.

    That would settle the matter, except for one difficulty:
    what I have just said seems to imply that I can never be in
    error. If everything that is in me comes from God, and he
    didn’t equip me with a capacity for making mistakes, doesn’t
    it follow that I can never go wrong in my beliefs? Well, I know
    by experience that I am greatly given to errors; but when I
    focus on God to the exclusion of everything else, I find in
    him no cause of error or falsity. In looking for the cause of
    my errors, I am helped by this thought: as well as having
    a real and positive idea of God (a being who is supremely

    perfect), I also have what you might call a negative idea
    of nothingness (that which is furthest from all perfection). I
    realize that I am somewhere in between God and nothingness,
    or between supreme being and non-being. Now, the positive
    reality that I have been given by the supreme being contains
    nothing that could lead me astray in my beliefs. I make
    mistakes, not surprisingly, because my nature involves
    nothingness or non-being—that is, because I am not myself
    the supreme being, and lack countless perfections. So error
    is not something real that depends on God, but is merely
    ·something negative, a lack·, a defect. There is, therefore,
    nothing positively error-producing in the faculty of judgment
    that God gave me. When I go wrong I do so because the
    faculty of true judgment that I have from God is in my case
    not free of all limitations, ·that is, because it partly involves
    nothingness·.

    That is still not quite right. For error isn’t a mere negation.
    ·Pebbles and glaciers lack knowledge, and in them that lack
    is a mere negation—the absence of something that there is
    no reason for them to possess. I have lacks of that kind
    too, mere negations such my lack of the ability to fly, or to
    multiply two 30-digit prime numbers in my head. But my
    tendency to error isn’t like that·. Rather, it is a privation,
    that is, a lack of some knowledge that I should have, ·which
    means that I still have a problem about how it relates to God·.
    When I think hard about God, it seems impossible that he
    should have given me a faculty that lacks some perfection
    that it should have. The more skilled the craftsman, the
    more perfect the thing that he makes; so one would expect
    something made by the supreme creator to be complete and
    perfect in every way. It is clear, furthermore, that God could
    have made me in such a way that I was never mistaken; and
    there is no doubt that he always chooses to do what is best.
    Does this show that my making mistakes is better than my

    18

    Meditations René Descartes Fourth Meditation

    not doing so?
    Thinking harder about this, ·three helpful thoughts come

    to me. Two concern our knowledge of God’s reasons gen-
    erally; the third is specifically about human error·. (1) I
    realize that it is no cause for surprise if I don’t always
    understand why God acts as he does. I may well find other
    things he has done whose reasons elude me; and that is
    no reason to doubt his existence. I am now aware that my
    nature is very weak and limited, whereas God’s nature is
    immense, incomprehensible and infinite; so of course he can
    do countless things whose reasons I can’t know. That alone
    is reason enough to give up, as totally useless, the attempt
    that physicists make to understand the world in terms of
    what things are for, ·that is, in terms of God’s purposes·.
    Only a very rash man would think he could discover what
    God’s impenetrable purposes are.

    (2) In estimating whether God’s works are perfect, we
    should look at the universe as a whole, not at created things
    one by one. Something that might seem very imperfect if it
    existed on its own has a function in relation to the rest of
    the universe, and may be perfect when seen in that light.
    My decision to doubt everything has left me sure of the
    existence of only two things, God and myself; but when I
    think about God’s immense power I have to admit that he
    did or could have made many things in addition to myself,
    so that there may be a universal scheme of things in which
    I have a place. ·If that is so, then judgments about what is
    perfect or imperfect in me should be made on the basis not
    just of my intrinsic nature but also of my role or function in
    the universe as a whole·.

    (3) My errors are the only evidence I have that I am
    imperfect. When I look more closely into these errors of
    mine, I discover that they have two co-operating causes—my
    faculty of knowledge and my faculty of choice or freedom of

    the will. My errors, that is, depend on both (a) my intellect
    and (b) my will. ·Let us consider these separately·. (a)
    The intellect doesn’t affirm or deny anything; its role is
    only to present me with ideas regarding which I can make
    judgments; so strictly speaking it doesn’t involve any error
    at all. There may be many existing things of which my
    intellect gives me no ideas, but it isn’t strictly correct to
    say that I am deprived of such ideas, as it would be if my
    nature somehow entitled me to have them. I can give no
    reason why God ought to have given me more ideas than
    he did. Just because I understand someone to be a skilled
    craftsman, I don’t infer that he ought to have put into each
    of his works all the perfections he can give to some of them.
    So all I can say is that there are some ideas that I don’t have;
    this is a purely negative fact about me ·like the fact that I
    can’t fly; it doesn’t mean that there is anything wrong with
    my nature·. (b) I can’t complain that God gave me a will
    or freedom of choice that isn’t extensive or perfect enough,
    since I know by experience that will is entirely without limits.
    My will is so perfect and so great that I can’t conceive of its
    becoming even greater and more perfect; it is a striking fact
    that this is true of •my will and not of •any other aspect of
    my nature. I can easily see that my faculty of understanding
    is finite, to put it mildly; and I immediately conceive of a
    much greater •understanding—indeed, of a supremely great
    and infinite one; and the fact that I can form such an idea
    shows me that God actually has such an understanding.
    Similarly, if I examine •memory and •imagination and the
    rest, I discover that in my case these faculties are weak and
    limited, while in God they are immeasurable. It is only the
    will, or freedom of choice, which I experience as so great
    that I can’t make sense of the idea of its being even greater:
    indeed, my thought of myself as being somehow like God
    depends primarily upon my will. God’s will is incomparably

    19

    Meditations René Descartes Fourth Meditation

    greater than mine in two respects: •it is accompanied by,
    and made firm and effective by, much more knowledge and
    power than I have; and •it has far more objects than my will
    does—·that is, God makes more choices and decisions than
    I do. But these comparisons—having to do with •the amount
    of knowledge that accompanies and helps the will, or with
    •the number of states of affairs to which it is applied—do
    not concern the will in itself, but rather its relations to
    other things·. When the will is considered ·not relationally,
    but· strictly in itself, God’s will does not seem any greater
    than mine. The will is simply one’s ability to do or not do
    something—to accept or reject a proposition, to pursue a
    goal or avoid something. More accurately: the ·freedom of
    the· will consists in the fact that when the intellect presents
    us with a candidate for acceptance or denial, or for pursuit
    or avoidance, we have no sense that we are pushed one way
    or the other by any external force. I can be free without
    being inclined both ways. Indeed, the more strongly I incline
    in one direction the more free my choice is—if my inclination
    comes from •natural knowledge (that is, from my seeing
    clearly that reasons of truth and goodness point that way)
    or from •divine grace (that is, from some mental disposition
    that God has given me). Freedom is never lessened—indeed
    it is increased and strengthened—by •natural knowledge and
    •divine grace. When no reason inclines me in one direction
    rather than another, I have a feeling of indifference—·that is,
    of its not mattering which way I go·—and that is the poorest
    kind of freedom. What it displays is freedom, considered not
    as a perfection but rather as a lack of knowledge—a kind of
    negation. If I always saw clearly what was true and good,
    I should never have to spend time thinking about what to
    believe or do; and then I would be wholly free although I was
    never in a state of indifference.

    So the power of willing that God has given me, being
    extremely broad in its scope and also perfect of its kind, is not
    the cause of my mistakes. Nor is my power of understanding
    to blame: God gave it to me, so there can be no error in
    its activities; when I understand something I undoubtedly
    understand it correctly. Well, then, where do my mistakes
    come from? Their source is the fact that my will has a wider
    scope than my intellect has, ·so that I am free to form beliefs
    on topics that I don’t understand·. Instead of ·behaving as I
    ought to, namely by· restricting my will to the territory that
    my understanding covers, ·that is, suspending judgment
    when I am not intellectually in control·, I let my will run
    loose, applying it to matters that I don’t understand. In such
    cases there is nothing to stop the will from veering this way
    or that, so it easily turns away from what is true and good.
    That is the source of my error and sin.

    Here is an example ·of how (1) the will’s behaviour when
    there is true understanding contrasts with (2) its behaviour
    when there isn’t·. (1) A while ago I asked whether anything
    in the world exists, and I came to realize that the fact of
    my raising this question shows quite clearly that I exist. I
    understood this so vividly that I couldn’t help judging that it
    was true. This was not the ‘couldn’t help’ that comes from
    being compelled by some external force. What happened was
    just this: a great light in the intellect was followed by a great
    inclination in the will. I was not in a state of indifference,
    ·feeling that I could as well go one way as the other·; but this
    lack of indifference was a measure of how spontaneous and
    free my belief was. ·It would have indicated unfreedom only
    if it had come from the compulsion of something external,
    rather than coming from within myself·. (2) As well as
    knowing that I exist, at least as a thinking thing, I have
    in my mind an idea of corporeal nature; and I am not sure
    whether my thinking nature—which makes me what I am—is

    20

    Meditations René Descartes Fourth Meditation

    the same as this corporeal nature or different from it. I take
    it that my intellect has not yet found any convincing reason
    for either answer; so I am indifferent with regard to this
    question—nothing pushes or pulls me towards one answer
    or the other, or indeed towards giving any answer.

    The will is indifferent not only when the intellect is
    wholly ignorant but also when it doesn’t have clear enough
    knowledge at the time when the will is trying to reach a
    decision. A probable conjecture may pull me one way; but
    when I realize that it is a mere conjecture and not a certain
    and indubitable reason, that in itself will push me the other
    way. My experience in the last few days confirms this: the
    mere fact that I found all my previous beliefs to be somewhat
    open to doubt was enough to switch me from confidently
    believing them to supposing them to be wholly false.

    If when I don’t perceive the truth vividly and clearly
    enough I simply suspend judgment, it’s clear that I am
    behaving correctly and avoiding error. It is a misuse of
    my free will to have an opinion in such cases: if I choose the
    wrong side I shall be in error; and even if I choose the right
    side, I shall be at fault because I’ll have come to the truth
    by sheer chance and not through a perception of my intellect.
    The latter, as the natural light shows me clearly, should be
    what influences my will when I affirm things. I have said
    that error is essentially a privation—a lack of something that
    I should have—and now I know what this privation consists
    in. It doesn’t lie in •the will that God has given me, or even
    in •the mode of operation that God has built into it; rather it
    consists in •my misuse of my will. ·Specifically, it consists in
    •my lack of restraint in the exercise of my will, when I form
    opinions on matters that I don’t clearly understand·.

    I can’t complain that God did not give me a greater power
    of understanding than he did: created intellects are naturally
    finite, and so they naturally lack understanding of many

    things. God has never owed me anything, so I should thank
    him for his great generosity to me, rather than feeling cheated
    because he did not give me everything.

    Nor can I reasonably complain that God gave me a will
    that extends more widely than my intellect. The will is a
    single unitary thing; its nature is such, it seems, that there
    could be no way of taking away parts of it. Anyway, should
    not the great extent of my will be a cause for further thanks
    to him who gave it to me?

    Finally, I must not complain that God consents to the
    acts of will in which I go wrong. What there is in these acts
    that comes from God is wholly true and good; and it is a
    perfection in me that I can perform them. Falsity and error
    are essentially a privation; and this privation isn’t something
    to which God consents, because it isn’t a thing at all. Indeed,
    when it is considered in relation to God as its cause, it isn’t
    really a privation but rather a mere negation. ·That is, it
    is a mere fact about something that is not the case; it does
    not involve the notion that it ought to be the case. I ought
    to restrain my will when I don’t understand, but it isn’t
    true that God ought to have forced such restraint on me·.
    God has given me the freedom to assent or not assent in
    cases where he did not give me clear understanding; he is
    surely not to blame for that. But I am to blame for misusing
    that freedom by coming to conclusions on matters that I
    don’t fully understand. Of course God easily could have
    arranged things so that, while keeping all my freedom and
    still being limited in what I understand, I never made a
    mistake. He could do this either by •giving me a vivid and
    clear understanding of everything that I was ever likely to
    think about; or by •forcing me always to remember that I
    ought not to form opinions on matters I don’t vividly and
    clearly understand. I can see that if God had made me this
    way, I would—considered just in myself, as if nothing else

    21

    Meditations René Descartes Fourth Meditation

    existed—have been more perfect than I actually am. But the
    universe as a whole may have some perfection that requires
    that some parts of it be capable of error while others are
    not, so that it would be a worse universe if all its parts were
    exactly alike ·in being immune from error·. I am not entitled
    to complain about God’s giving me a lower role in his scheme
    of things ·by selecting me as one of the creatures that isn’t
    protected from error·.

    What is more, even if I have no power to avoid error by
    •having a vivid perception of everything I have to think about,
    I can avoid it simply by •remembering to withhold judgment
    on anything that isn’t clear to me. I admit to having the
    weakness that I can’t keep my attention fixed on a single
    item of knowledge (·such as the no-judgment-when-clarity-of-
    perception-is-lacking rule·); but by attentive and repeated
    meditation I can get myself to remember it as often as the
    need arises, and thus to get into the habit of avoiding error.

    This is where man’s greatest and most important perfec-

    tion is to be found; so today’s meditation, with its enquiry
    into the cause of error, has been very profitable. I must be
    right in my explanation of the cause of error. If I restrain
    my will so that I form opinions only on what the intellect
    vividly and clearly reveals, I cannot possibly go wrong. Here
    is why. Every vivid and clear perception is undoubtedly
    something real and positive; so it can’t come from nothing,
    and must come from God. He is supremely perfect; it would
    be downright contradictory to suppose that he is a deceiver.
    So the vivid and clear perception must be true. So today I
    have learned not only how to avoid error but also how to
    arrive at the truth. It is beyond question that I shall reach
    the truth if I think hard enough about •the things that I
    perfectly understand, keeping them separate from •all the
    other matters in which my thoughts are more confused and
    obscure. That is what I shall be really careful to do from now
    on.

    22

      Third Meditation
      Fourth Meditation

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    ‘But with regard to your main line of thought’ (I continued)
    ‘there occurs to me a difficulty that I shall just propose to
    you without insisting on it, lest it lead into reasonings of
    too subtle and delicate a nature. Briefly, then, I very much
    doubt that it’s possible for a cause to be known only by its
    effect (as you have supposed all through) or to be so singular
    and particular that it has no parallel or similarity with any
    other cause or object we have ever observed. It is only when
    two kinds of objects are found to be constantly conjoined
    that we can infer one from the other; and if we encountered
    an effect that was entirely singular, and couldn’t be placed
    in any known kind, I don’t see that we could conjecture
    or infer anything at all concerning its cause. If experience
    and observation and analogy really are the only guides we

    can reasonably follow in inferences of this sort, both the
    effect and the cause must have some similarity to other
    effects and causes that we already know and have found
    often to be conjoined with each other. I leave it to you to
    think through the consequences of this principle. I shall
    merely remark that, as the antagonists of Epicurus always
    suppose that the universe, an effect that is quite singular
    and unparalleled, is proof of a god, a cause no less singular
    and unparalleled, your reasonings about this seem at least
    to merit our attention. There is, I admit, some difficulty in
    grasping how we can ever return from the cause to the effect,
    and by reasoning from our ideas of the cause infer anything
    new about the effect.’

    Section 12: The sceptical philosophy

    Philosophical arguments proving the existence of a god and
    refuting the fallacies of atheists outnumber the arguments
    on any other topic. Yet most religious philosophers still
    disagree about whether any man can be so blinded as to
    be an atheist. How shall we reconcile these contradictions?
    The knights-errant who wandered about to clear the world
    of dragons and giants never had the least doubt that these
    monsters existed!

    The sceptic is another enemy of religion who naturally
    arouses the indignation of all religious authorities and of
    the more solemn philosophers; yet it’s certain that nobody
    ever met such an absurd creature ·as a sceptic·, or talked
    with a man who had no opinion on any subject, practical

    or theoretical. So the question naturally arises: What is
    meant by ‘sceptic’? And how far it is possible to push these
    philosophical principles of doubt and uncertainty?

    Descartes and others have strongly recommended one
    kind of scepticism, to be practised in advance of philosophy
    or any other studies. It preserves us, they say, against
    error and rash judgment. It recommends that we should
    doubt not only all our former opinions and principles but
    also our very faculties. The reliability of our faculties, these
    philosophers say, is something we must be assured of by a
    chain of reasoning, deduced from some first principle that
    cannot possibly be fallacious or deceitful. But there is no
    such first principle that has an authority above others that

    77

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    are self-evident and convincing. And even if there were
    one, we couldn’t advance a step beyond it except by using
    those very faculties that we are supposed to be calling into
    question. Cartesian doubt, therefore, if someone could attain
    to it (as plainly nobody could), would be entirely incurable,
    and no reasoning could ever bring us to confident beliefs
    about anything.

    However, a more moderate degree of such scepticism can
    be quite reasonable, and is a necessary preparation for the
    study of philosophy: it makes us impartial in our judgments
    and weans our minds from prejudices that we may have
    arrived at thoughtlessly or taken in through education. If we

    •begin with clear and self-evident principles,
    •move forward cautiously, getting a secure footing at
    each step,

    •check our conclusions frequently, and
    •carefully examine their consequences,

    we shall move slowly, and not get far; but these are the only
    methods by which we can hope ever to establish conclusions
    which we are sure are true and which will last.

    Another kind of scepticism has arisen out of scientific
    enquiries that are supposed to have shown that human
    mental faculties are either absolutely deceitful or not capable
    of reaching fixed conclusions about any of the puzzling topics
    on which they are commonly employed. Even our senses
    are questioned by a certain kind of philosopher; and the
    maxims of everyday life are subjected to the same doubt
    as are the deepest principles of metaphysics and theology.
    Some philosophers accept these paradoxical tenets (if they
    may be called tenets), while many others try to refute them;
    so it’s natural for us to wonder about them, and to look for
    the arguments on which they may be based.

    I needn’t dwell on the well-worn arguments that sceptics
    have used down the ages to discredit the senses, such as

    the arguments drawn from the untrustworthy nature of our
    sense organs, which very often lead us astray: the crooked
    appearance of an oar half in water, the different ways an
    object can look depending on how far away it is, the double
    images that arise from pressing one eye, and many other
    such phenomena. These sceptical points serve only to prove
    that the senses, taken on their own, shouldn’t automatically
    be trusted, and that if they are to serve as criteria of truth
    and falsehood we must adjust the answers they give us by
    bringing reason to bear on facts about •the nature of the
    medium—·e.g. the water through which we see the lower half
    of the oar·—•the distance of the object, and •the condition of
    the sense organ. But other arguments against the senses go
    deeper, and are harder to meet.

    It seems clear that •we humans are naturally, instinc-
    tively inclined to trust our senses, and that •without any
    reasoning—indeed, almost before the use of reason—we take
    it that there is an external universe that doesn’t depend
    on our perceiving it and would have existed if there had
    never been any perceiving creatures or if we had all been
    annihilated. Even the animals are governed by a similar
    opinion, and maintain this belief in external objects in all
    their thoughts, plans and actions.

    It also seems clear that when men follow this blind and
    powerful instinct of nature they always suppose that •the
    very images that their senses present to them are •the
    external objects that they perceive; it never crosses their
    minds that •sensory images are merely representations of
    •external objects. This very table that we see as white
    and feel as hard is believed to exist independently of our
    perception, and to be something external to our mind, which
    perceives it. Our presence doesn’t bring it into existence,
    and our absence doesn’t annihilate it. It stays in existence
    (we think), complete and unchanging, independent of any

    78

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    facts about intelligent beings who perceive it or think about
    it.

    But the slightest philosophy is enough to destroy this
    basic belief that all men have. For philosophy teaches us
    that images (or perceptions) are the only things that can
    ever be present to the mind, and that the senses serve only
    to bring these images before the mind and cannot put our
    minds into any immediate relation with external objects.
    The table that we see seems to shrink as we move away
    from it; but the real table that exists independently of us
    doesn’t alter; so what was present to the mind wasn’t the
    real table but only an image of it. These are the obvious
    dictates of reason; and no-one who thinks about it has ever
    doubted that when we say ‘this house’ and ‘that tree’ the
    things we are referring to are nothing but perceptions in the
    mind—fleeting copies or representations of other things that
    are independent of us and don’t change.

    To that extent, then, reason compels us to contradict or
    depart from the basic instincts of nature, and to adopt a
    new set of views about the evidence of our senses. ·These
    views amount to a philosophical system according to which
    (1) we perceive only images, not external objects, but (2)
    there are external objects, and images represent them·. But
    when philosophy tries to justify this new system, and put
    to rest the carping objections of the sceptics, it finds itself
    in an awkward position ·regarding the claim (2) that there
    are external objects that our images represent·. Philosophy
    can no longer rely on the idea that natural instincts are
    infallible and irresistible, for those instincts led us to a
    quite different system that is admitted to be fallible and
    even wrong. And to justify ·the external-object part of·
    this purported philosophical system by a chain of clear
    and convincing argument—or even by any appearance of
    argument—is more than anyone can do.

    By what argument can it be proved that the perceptions
    of the mind must be caused by •external objects that are
    perfectly distinct from them and yet similar to them (if that
    were possible), rather than arising from •the energy of the
    mind itself, or from •the activities of some invisible and un-
    known spirit, or from •some other cause still more unknown
    to us? It is admitted that many of these perceptions—e.g.
    in dreams, madness, and other diseases—don’t in fact arise
    from anything external, ·so how could we prove that others
    do arise from something external·? In any case, we are
    utterly unable to explain how a body could so act on a mind
    as to convey an image of itself to a mental substance whose
    nature is supposed to be so different from—even contrary
    to—its own nature.

    Are the perceptions of the senses produced by external
    objects that resemble them? This is a question of fact.
    Where shall we look for an answer to it? To experience,
    surely, as we do with all other questions of that kind. But
    here experience is and must be entirely silent. The mind
    never has anything present to it except the perceptions, and
    can’t possibly experience their connection with objects. The
    belief in such a connection, therefore, has no foundation in
    reasoning ·because the reasoning would have to start from
    something known through experience·.

    We might try to prove that our senses are truthful by
    appealing to the truthfulness of God, but that would be a
    strange direction for the argument to take, ·for two reasons·.
    (1) If the fallibility of our senses implied that God is untruth-
    ful, then our senses would never mislead us; because it isn’t
    possible that God should ever deceive. (2) Anyway, once the
    external world has been called in question we are left with
    no arguments to prove that God exists or to show what his
    attributes are.

    The deeper and more philosophical sceptics, trying to cast

    79

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    doubt on all subjects of human knowledge and enquiry, will
    always triumph when it comes to the question of external
    bodies. ‘Do you follow your natural instincts and inclina-
    tions’, they may say, ‘when you affirm the truthfulness of
    your senses? But those instincts lead you to believe that the
    perception or image that you experience is itself the external
    object. Do you reject that view, in order to accept the more
    reasonable opinion that perceptions are only representations
    of something external? In that case you are departing from
    your natural inclinations and more obvious opinions; and
    yet you still can’t satisfy your reason, which can never find
    any convincing argument from experience to prove that your
    perceptions are connected with external objects.’

    Another sceptical line of thought—somewhat like that
    one—has deep philosophical roots, and might be worth
    attending to if there were any point in digging that far
    down in order to discover arguments that can be of so
    little serious use. All modern enquirers agree that all the
    sensible qualities of objects—such as hard, soft, hot, cold,
    white, black, etc.—are merely secondary; they don’t exist in
    the objects themselves (it is believed), and are perceptions
    of the mind with no external pattern or model that they
    represent. If this is granted regarding secondary qualities, it
    also holds for the supposed primary qualities of extension
    and solidity, which are no more entitled to be called ‘primary’
    than the others are. The idea of extension comes purely
    from the senses of sight and touch; and if all the qualities
    that are perceived by the senses are in the mind rather than
    in the object, that must hold also for the idea of extension,

    which wholly depends on sensible ideas, i.e. on the ideas of
    secondary qualities. ·To see that something is extended, you
    have to see colours; to feel that it is extended, you have to feel
    hardness or softness·. The only escape from this conclusion
    is to assert that we get the ideas of those ‘primary’ qualities
    through abstraction; but the doctrine of abstraction turns
    out under careful scrutiny to be unintelligible, and even
    absurd. An extension that is neither tangible nor visible can’t
    possibly be conceived; and a tangible or visible extension
    that is neither hard nor soft, black nor white, is equally
    beyond the reach of human conception. Let anyone try to
    conceive a triangle in general, which has no particular length
    or proportion of sides, and he will soon see the absurdity of
    all the scholastic notions concerning abstraction and general
    ideas.13

    Thus the first philosophical objection to the belief in
    external objects is this: If the belief is based on natural
    instinct it is contrary to reason; and if it is attributed to
    reason it is contrary to natural instinct, and anyway isn’t
    supported by any rational evidence that would convince
    an impartial person who thought about it. The second
    objection goes further and represents this belief as contrary
    to reason—at least if reason says that all sensible qualities
    are in the mind and not in the object. Deprive matter of
    all its intelligible qualities, both primary and secondary,
    and you in a way annihilate it and leave only a certain
    mysterious something as the cause of our perceptions, a
    notion so imperfect that no sceptic will think it worthwhile
    to argue against it.

    13This argument is drawn from Dr. Berkeley; and indeed most of the writings of that able author form the best lessons of scepticism that are to be found
    either among the ancient or modern philosophers. Yet on his title-page he claims, no doubt sincerely, to have composed his book against the sceptics
    as well as against atheists and free-thinkers. But though his arguments are otherwise intended, they are all in fact merely sceptical. This is shown by
    the fact that they cannot be answered yet do not convince. Their only effect is to cause the momentary bewilderment and confusion that is the result of
    scepticism.

    80

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    Part 2

    There may seem to be something wild about the sceptics’
    attempt to destroy reason by argument and reasoning; yet
    that’s what all their enquiries and disputes amount to. They
    try to find objections both to our abstract reasonings and to
    reasonings about matter of fact and existence.

    The chief objection to abstract reasonings comes from
    the ideas of space and time. Those ideas, when viewed
    carelessly as we view them in everyday life, are very clear
    and intelligible; but when we look into them more closely
    they turn out to involve principles that seem full of absurdity
    and contradiction. No priestly dogmas, invented on purpose
    to tame and subdue the rebellious reason of mankind, ever
    shocked common sense more than the doctrine of the infinite
    divisibility of extension, with its consequences that are
    ceremoniously paraded by geometers and metaphysicians as
    though they were something to be proud of. ·For example·:

    A real quantity that is infinitely less than any finite
    quantity, and contains quantities that are infinitely
    less than itself, and so on to infinity—

    this bold, enormous edifice is too weighty to be supported by
    any demonstration, because it offends against the clearest
    and most natural principles of human reason.14

    But what makes the matter more extraordinary is that
    these seemingly absurd opinions are supported by a chain of
    reasoning that seems clear and utterly natural, and we can’t
    accept the premises without accepting the conclusions. The
    geometrical proofs regarding the properties of circles and
    triangles are as convincing and satisfactory as they could

    possibly be; but if we accept them, how can we deny that
    •the angle of contact between any circle and its tan-
    gent is infinitely less than any angle between straight
    lines, and that as the circle gets larger •the angle of
    contact becomes still smaller, ad infinitum?

    The demonstration of these principles seems as flawless as
    the one proving that the three angles of a triangle equal
    180 degrees, though the latter conclusion is natural and
    easy while the former is pregnant with contradiction and
    absurdity. Reason here seems to be thrown into a kind of
    bewilderment and indecision which, without prompting from
    any sceptic, makes it unsure of itself and of the ground
    it walks on. It sees a bright light that illuminates some
    places; but right next to them there is the most profound
    darkness. Caught between these, reason is so dazzled and
    confused that there is hardly any topic on which it can reach
    a confident conclusion.

    The absurdity of these bold conclusions of the abstract
    sciences seems to become even more conspicuous with
    regard to time than it is with extension. An infinite number
    of real parts of time, passing in succession and gone through
    ·completely·, one after another—this appears to be such an
    obvious contradiction that nobody, one would think, could
    bring himself to believe it unless his judgment had been
    corrupted, rather than being improved, by the sciences.

    Yet still reason must remain restless and unquiet, even
    with regard to the scepticism it is driven to by these seeming
    absurdities and contradictions. We can’t make sense of the
    thought that a clear, distinct idea might contain something

    14Whatever disputes there may be about mathematical points, we must allow that there are physical points—that is, parts of extension that cannot be
    divided or lessened either by the eye or imagination. So these images that are present to the imagination or the senses are absolutely indivisible, and
    consequently must be regarded by mathematicians as infinitely less than any real part of extension; yet nothing appears more certain to reason than that
    an infinite number of them composes an infinite extension. This holds with even more force of an infinite number of the infinitely small parts of extension
    that are still supposed to be, themselves, infinitely divisible.

    81

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    that is contradictory to itself or to some other clear, distinct
    idea; this is indeed as absurd a proposition as we can
    think of. So this scepticism about some of the paradoxical
    conclusions of mathematics—·a scepticism which implies
    that some of our clear, distinct ideas contradict others·—is
    itself something we must be sceptical about, approaching it
    in a doubting, hesitant frame of mind.15

    Sceptical objections to reasonings about matters of fact
    are of two kinds—(1) everyday informal objections, and (2)
    philosophical ones. (1) The informal objections are based
    on •the natural weakness of human understanding, •the
    contradictory opinions that have been held at different times
    and in different countries, •the variations of our judgment
    in sickness and health, youth and old age, prosperity and
    adversity, •the perpetual differences of opinion between
    different individuals—and many other considerations of that
    kind, but there is no need to go on about them. These
    objections are weak. For as in ordinary life we reason every
    moment regarding fact and existence, and can’t survive
    without continually doing so, no objections that are based on
    this procedure can be sufficient to undermine it. The great
    subverter of excessive scepticism is action, practical projects,
    the occupations of everyday life. Sceptical principles may
    flourish and triumph in the philosophy lecture-room, where
    it is indeed hard if not impossible to refute them. But as soon
    as they •come out of the shadows, •are confronted by the real

    things that our beliefs and emotions are addressed to, and
    thereby •come into conflict with the more powerful principles
    of our nature, sceptical principles vanish like smoke and
    leave the most determined sceptic in the same ·believing·
    condition as other mortals.

    (2) The sceptic, therefore, had better stay in the area
    where he does best, and present the philosophical objections
    whose roots run deeper ·than the facts on which the informal
    objections are based·. These seem to provide him with plenty
    of victories. He can rightly insist

    •that all our evidence for any matter of fact that lies
    beyond the testimony of sense or memory is entirely
    based on the relation of cause and effect; item •that
    our only idea of this relation is the idea of two kinds
    of event that have frequently been associated with one
    another; item •that we have no argument to convince
    us that kinds of event that we have often found to be
    associated in the past will be so in future;

    •and that what leads us to this inference is merely
    custom—a certain instinct of our nature—which it is
    indeed hard to resist but which like any other instinct
    may be wrong and deceitful.

    While the sceptic presses these points, he is in a strong
    position, and seems to destroy all assurance and conviction,
    at least for a while. (In a way, what he is showing is not
    his strength but rather his and everyone’s weakness!) These

    15We might be able to avoid these absurdities and contradictions if we admitted that there is no such thing as abstract or general ideas, properly speaking;
    but that all general ideas are really particular ones attached to a general term which brings to mind other particular ideas which in some way resemble
    the idea that is present to the mind. Thus when the word ‘horse’ is pronounced, we immediately form the idea of a black or a white animal of a particular
    size and shape; but as that word is also usually applied to animals of other colours, shapes and sizes, these ideas are easily recalled even when they
    are not actually present to the imagination; so that our reasoning can proceed in the same way as if they were actually present. If this is accepted—and
    it seems reasonable—it follows that the ideas of quantity that mathematicians reason with are particular ones, i.e. ideas of the kind that come through
    the senses and imagination; in which case those ideas cannot be infinitely divisible. At this point I merely drop that hint, without developing it in detail.
    It does seem to be the readiest solution for these difficulties. We need some solution if the mathematicians are not to be exposed to the ridicule and
    contempt of ignorant people.

    82

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    arguments of his could be developed at greater length, if
    there were any reason to think that doing this would be
    useful to mankind.

    That brings me to the chief and most unanswerable
    objection to excessive scepticism, namely that no lasting
    good can ever result from it while it remains in its full force
    and vigour. We need only ask such a sceptic: ‘What do
    you want? What do you intend to achieve through your
    sceptical arguments?’ He is immediately at a loss, and
    doesn’t know what to answer. A Copernican or Ptolemaic
    who supports a particular system of astronomy may hope
    to produce in his audience beliefs that will remain constant
    and long-lasting. A Stoic or Epicurean displays principles
    which may not last, but which have an effect on conduct
    and behaviour. But a Pyrrhonian [= ‘extreme sceptic’; Pyrrho
    was the first notable sceptic in ancient Greece] cannot expect his
    philosophy to have any steady influence on the mind, and
    if it did, he couldn’t expect the influence to benefit society.
    On the contrary, if he will admit anything he must admit
    that if his principles were universally and steadily accepted,
    all human life would come to an end. All discourse and all
    action would immediately cease; and men would remain in
    a total lethargy until their miserable lives came to an end
    through lack of food, drink and shelter. It is true that this
    fatal outcome is not something we really have to fear: nature
    is always too strong for principle. And though a Pyrrhonian
    may throw himself or others into a momentary bewilderment
    and confusion by his deep arguments, the first and most
    trivial event in life will put all his doubts and worries to
    flight, and will leave him—in every aspect of his actions
    and beliefs—in just the same position as any other kind
    of philosopher, and indeed the same as someone who had
    never concerned himself with philosophical researches at
    all. When he awakes from his dream, the sceptic will be the

    first to join in the laughter against himself and to admit that
    all his objections are mere amusement and can only serve
    to show how odd and freakish the situation of mankind is:
    we must act and reason and believe, but however hard we
    try we can’t find a satisfactory basis for those operations
    and can’t remove the objections that can be brought against
    them.

    Part 3

    There is indeed a milder kind of scepticism that may be
    both durable and useful. It may be a part of what results
    from Pyrrhonism, or excessive scepticism, when its undis-
    criminating doubts are modified a little by common sense
    and reflection. Most people are naturally apt to be positive
    and dogmatic in their opinions; they see only one side of
    an issue, have no idea of any arguments going the other
    way, and recklessly commit themselves to the principles
    that seem to them right, with no tolerance for those who
    hold opposing views. Pausing to reflect, or balancing ar-
    guments pro and con, only serves to get them muddled,
    to damp down their emotions, and to delay their actions.
    They are very uncomfortable in this state, and are thus
    impatient to escape from it; and they think they can keep
    away from it—the further the better—by the violence of their
    assertions and the obstinacy of their beliefs. But if these
    dogmatic reasoners became aware of how frail the human
    understanding is, even at its best and most cautious, this
    awareness would naturally lead to their being less dogmatic
    and outspoken, less sure of themselves and less prejudiced
    against antagonists. The illiterate may reflect on the fact
    that learned people, despite all their advantages of study and
    reflection, are often cautious and tentative in their opinions.
    If any of the learned should be temperamentally inclined to

    83

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    pride and obstinacy, a small dose of Pyrrhonism might lessen
    their pride by showing them that the few advantages they
    have over other (·unlearned·) men don’t amount to much
    when compared with the universal perplexity and confusion
    that is inherent in human nature. There is, in short, a degree
    of doubt and caution and modesty that every reasoner ought
    to have at all times in every context of enquiry.

    Another kind of moderate scepticism that may be useful
    to mankind, and may be the natural result of Pyrrhonian
    doubts, is the limitation of our enquiries to the subjects
    that our narrow human understanding is best equipped to
    deal with. The imagination of man naturally soars into the
    heights: it rejoices in whatever is remote and extraordinary,
    and runs off uncontrollably into the most distant parts
    of space and time in order to avoid the familiar objects
    that it has become used to. A faculty of judgment that
    is working properly proceeds in the opposite way: it avoids
    all distant and high enquiries, and confines itself to subjects
    that we meet with in everyday activities and experience,
    leaving grander topics to poets and orators or to priests
    and politicians. The best way for us to be brought into
    this healthy frame of mind is for us to become thoroughly
    convinced of the force of Pyrrhonian doubt, and to see that
    our only possible escape from it is through the strong power
    of natural instinct. Those who are drawn to philosophy will
    still continue their researches, attracted by the immediate
    pleasure of this activity and by their realization that philo-
    sophical doctrines are nothing but organized and corrected
    versions of the thoughts of everyday life. But they will never
    be tempted to go beyond everyday life so long as they bear
    in mind the imperfection—the narrowness of scope, and the
    inaccuracy—of their own faculties. Given that we can’t even
    provide a satisfactory reason why we believe after a thousand
    experiences that a stone will fall or fire will burn, can we ever

    be confident in any of our beliefs about the origin of worlds,
    or about the unfolding of nature from and to eternity?

    The slightest enquiry into the natural powers of the
    human mind, and the comparison of •those powers with
    •the topics the mind studies, will be enough to make anyone
    willing to limit the scope of his enquiries in the way I have
    proposed. Let us then consider what are the proper subjects
    of science and enquiry.

    It seems to me that the only objects of the abstract
    sciences—the ones whose results are rigorously proved—are
    quantity and number, and that it’s mere sophistry and
    illusion to try to extend this more perfect sort of knowledge
    beyond these bounds. The component parts of quantity
    and number are entirely similar; ·for example, the area of
    a given triangle is made of the same elements as the area
    of a given square, so that the question of whether the two
    areas are equal can at least come up·. For this reason, the
    relations amongst the parts of quantity and number become
    intricate and involved; and nothing can be more intriguing,
    as well as useful, than to trace in various ways their equality
    or inequality through their different appearances. But all
    other ideas are obviously distinct and different from each
    other; and so with them we can never go further—however
    hard we try—than to observe this diversity and come to
    the immediate, obvious conclusion that one thing is not
    another. If there is any difficulty in these decisions, it
    proceeds entirely from the indeterminate meaning of words,
    which is corrected by juster definitions. That the square on
    the hypotenuse is equal to the squares of the other two sides
    can’t be known without a train of reasoning and enquiry. But
    to convince us that where there is no property there can be no
    injustice it is only necessary to define the terms and explain
    ‘injustice’ to be ‘a violation of property’. This proposition
    is indeed merely an imperfect definition. Similarly with

    84

    First Enquiry David Hume 12: The sceptical philosophy

    all those purported reasonings that may be found in every
    other branch of learning except the sciences of quantity and
    number. The latter sciences, it’s safe to say, are the only
    proper objects of knowledge and demonstration.

    All other enquiries of men regard only matter of fact
    and existence; and these obviously can’t be demonstrated.
    Whatever is the case may not be the case. No negation
    of a fact can involve a contradiction. The nonexistence of
    any existing thing is as clear and distinct an idea as its
    existence. The proposition which affirms it not to exist, even
    if it is quite false, is just as conceivable and intelligible as
    that which affirms it to exist. The case is different with
    the sciences properly so called [Hume means: the mathematical
    sciences]. Every mathematical proposition that isn’t true is
    confused and unintelligible. That the cube root of 64 is equal
    to the half of 10 is a false proposition and can never be
    distinctly conceived. But that Caesar never existed may be
    a false proposition but still it’s perfectly conceivable and
    implies no contradiction.

    It follows that the existence of any thing can only be
    proved by arguments from its cause or its effect; and such
    arguments are based entirely on experience. If we reason a
    priori, anything may appear able to produce anything. The
    falling of a pebble may, for all we know, extinguish the sun;
    or the wish of a man may control the planets in their orbits.

    Only experience teaches us the nature and limits of cause
    and effect, and enables us to infer the existence of one object
    from that of another.16

    Such is the foundation of factual reasoning, which forms

    the greater part of human knowledge and is the source of all
    human action and behaviour.

    Factual reasonings concern either particular or general
    facts. Everyday practical thinking is concerned only with the
    former, as is the whole of history, geography and astronomy.

    The sciences that treat of general facts are politics, natu-
    ral philosophy [= ‘physics’], physic [= ‘medicine’], chemistry, etc.
    where the qualities, causes and effects of a whole species of
    objects are investigated.

    Divinity or theology proves the existence of a god and the
    immortality of souls, so the reasonings that compose it partly
    concern particular facts and partly general ones. In so far as
    it is supported by experience, theology has a foundation in
    reason, but its best and most solid foundation is faith and
    divine revelation.

    Morals and ·artistic· criticism are in the domain of taste
    and feeling rather than of intellectual thought. Beauty,
    whether moral or natural, is felt rather than perceived. If we
    do reason about it and try to fix standards of judgment, we
    must bring in facts that can be the objects of reasoning and
    enquiry—e.g. facts about the general taste of mankind.

    When we go through libraries, convinced of these princi-
    ples, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any
    volume—of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance—let
    us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning about quantity
    or number? No. Does it contain any experiential reasoning
    about matters of fact and existence? No. Then throw it in
    the fire, for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.

    16That impious maxim of the ancient philosophy, Ex nihilo, nihil fit [From nothing, nothing is made], which was supposed to rule out the creation of matter,
    ceases to be a secure axiom according to this philosophy. Not only might the will of the supreme being create matter; but for all we know a priori it might
    be created by the will of any other being, or by any other cause that the most fanciful imagination can assign.

    85

    Calculate your order
    275 words
    Total price: $0.00

    Top-quality papers guaranteed

    54

    100% original papers

    We sell only unique pieces of writing completed according to your demands.

    54

    Confidential service

    We use security encryption to keep your personal data protected.

    54

    Money-back guarantee

    We can give your money back if something goes wrong with your order.

    Enjoy the free features we offer to everyone

    1. Title page

      Get a free title page formatted according to the specifics of your particular style.

    2. Custom formatting

      Request us to use APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, or any other style for your essay.

    3. Bibliography page

      Don’t pay extra for a list of references that perfectly fits your academic needs.

    4. 24/7 support assistance

      Ask us a question anytime you need to—we don’t charge extra for supporting you!

    Calculate how much your essay costs

    Type of paper
    Academic level
    Deadline
    550 words

    How to place an order

    • Choose the number of pages, your academic level, and deadline
    • Push the orange button
    • Give instructions for your paper
    • Pay with PayPal or a credit card
    • Track the progress of your order
    • Approve and enjoy your custom paper

    Ask experts to write you a cheap essay of excellent quality

    Place an order