Key Elements of Cybernetics Discussion

Our readings and discussions this week bring us into the early history of cybernetics, as first envisioned and described by Norbert Wiener.  Norbert Wiener coined the term “cybernetics” and was primarily responsible for popularizing it, first in the technically complex volume Cybernetics: Or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine (1948) and then in a volume written for nonspecialists titled The Human Use of Human Beings: Cybernetics and Society (1950).  One particularly interesting thing to pay attention to is Wiener’s choice and deployment of animal and machine analogies, by which he seeks to explain far more complex and scientific ideas.  What do these analogies and examples reveal about Wiener’s worldview and conceptualization of human society?  What do they suggest about his understanding of machines and their role in human society?

Thomas Rid’s popular history acknowledges Wiener’s conceptual contributions, but also points out that many of the technologies and techniques now associated with cybernetics actually predated and developed independent of Wiener’s research and publications.  Moreover, though we closely associate Wiener’s name with cybernetics, he was far from the only individual to play an early role in defining the scope and meaning of the discipline.  Competing visions emerged from the fields of neurophysiology and computer science, suggesting that cybernetics as a discourse was from the outset a matter of furious debate.  Understanding the terms of that early debate will provide us a framework for understanding the complicated and incredibly diverse paths cyberneticians were later to explore.

To begin, I’d like to invite us to discuss in this forum some of the basic ideas involved in cybernetic discourses.

Drawing on the readings and our class discussion, please take up one of the following issue clusters (or identify one of your own):

the science of control, control systems, information flow, and information transfer

prediction, probability, statistics, modeling, simulations

feedback, negative feedback, self-adapting machines, homeostasis

the human-machine connection (or distinction), human and machine as analogies for each other, anthropomorphic machines

boundaries, transgressions, blurring, cyborgs, the Turing test

  • liberal humanism, selfhood, autonomy, human values, Wiener’s principled stand (“A Scientist Rebels”)
  • logic, binary code, digitization, digital representation, telephone switching circuitry

  • cybernetic control systems, military cybernetics, biocybernetics, state systems of control, servomechanisms, robot wars
  • Readings Attached.

    https://drive.google.com/file/d/1LpKCO2fqBn5xv1uWZ…

    ·      Rid, Thomas.

  • pp. 8-36 in Chapter 1: “Control and Communication at War”
  • pp. 43-63 in Chapter 2: “Cybernetics”

  • Wiener, Norbert.  Selections from
  • Chapter 1: “Cybernetics in History” (pp. 15-27)

  • Chapter 3: “Rigidity and Learning: Two Patterns of Communicative Behavior” (pp. 48-73
  • Recommended: Ashby, Ross.  Selections from

  • Chapter 13: “Regulating the Very Large System” (pp. 244-264)
  • THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    This is one of the fundamental documents of our time, a period
    characterized by the concepts of ‘information’ and ‘communications’. Norbert Wiener, a child prodigy and a great mathematician,
    coined the term ‘cybernetics’ to characterize a very general science
    of ‘control and communication in the animal and machine’. It
    brought together concepts from engineering, the study of the
    nervous system and statistical mechanics (e.g. entropy). From these
    he developed concepts that have become pervasive through science
    (especially biology and computing) and common parlance: ‘information’, ‘message’, ‘feedback’ and ‘control’. He wrote, ‘the
    thought of every age is reflected in its technique . . . If the
    seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries are the age of clocks,
    and the later eighteenth and nineteenth centuries constitute the age
    of steam engines, the present time is the age of communication and
    control.’
    In this volume Norbert Wiener spells out his theories for the
    general reader and reflects on the social issues raised by the
    dramatically increasing role of science and technology in the new
    age – the age in which we are now deeply and problematically
    embroiled. His cautionary remarks arc as relevant now as they were
    when the book first appeared in the 1950s.
    Norbert Wiener (1894-1964), Professor of Mathematics at the
    Massachusetts Institute of Technology from 1919 onwards, wrote
    numerous books on mathematics and engineering. Having developed methods useful to the military during World War Two, he
    later refused to do such work during the Cold War, while proposing
    non-military models of cybernetics.
    THE HUMAN USE
    OF HUMAN BEINGS
    CYBERNETICS
    AND SOCIETY
    NORBERT WIENER
    With a new Introduction bj1
    Steve J. Heims
    FN
    ‘an association in which the free development of each is the
    condition of the free development of all’
    FREE ASSOCIATION BOOKS I LONDON I 1989
    Published in Great Britain 1989 by
    Free Association Books
    26 Freegrove Road
    London N7 9RQ
    First published 1950; 1954, Houghton Mifflin
    Copyright,1950,1954byNorbenWiener
    Introduction © Steve J. Heims 1989
    British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
    Wiener, Norbert, 1894-1964
    The human use of human beings: cybernetics
    and society
    I. Cybernetics. Sociological perspectives
    I. Title
    306′.46
    ISBN 1-85343-075-7
    Printed and bound in Great Britain by
    Bookcraft, Midsomer Nonon, Avon
    To the memory of my father
    LEO WIENER
    formerly Professor of Slavic Languages
    at Harvard University
    my closest mentor and dearest antagonist
    ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
    Part of a chapter has already appeared in the Philosop~J’ of Science
    The author wishes to acknowledge permission which the publishe1
    of this journal has given him to reprint the material.
    CONTENTS
    BIOGRAPHICAL NoTES
    INTRODUCTION BY STEVE]. HEIMS
    APPENDIX
    II
    III
    IV
    v
    VI
    VII
    VIII
    IX
    X
    XI
    Preface
    Cybernetics in History
    Progress and Entropy
    Rigidity and Learning: Two Patterns
    of Communicative Behavior
    The Mechanism and History of
    Language
    Organization as the Message
    Law and Communication
    Communication, Secrecy, and Social
    Policy
    Role of the Intellectual and the
    Scientist
    The First and the Second Industrial
    Revolution
    Some Communication Machines
    and Their Future
    Language, Confusion, and Jam
    Index
    ix
    xi
    XXV
    7
    15
    28
    48
    74
    95
    105
    112
    131
    136
    163
    187
    194
    BIOGRAPHICAL NOTES
    NoRBERT WIEI’ER, born in 1894, was educated at Tufts College,
    Massachusetts, and Harvard University, Massachusetts, where he
    received his Ph.D. at the age of nineteen. He continued his studies
    at Cornell, Columbia, in England at Cambridge University, then at
    Gottingen and Copenhagen. He taught at Harvard and the University of Maine and in 1919 joined the staff of the Massachusetts
    Institute of Technology, where he was Professor of Mathematics.
    He was joint recipient of the Bocher Prize of the American
    Mathematical Society in 1933, and in 1936 was one of the seven
    American delegates to the International Congress of Mathematicians in Oslo. Dr Wiener served as Research Professor of
    Mathematics at the National Tsing Hua University in Peking in
    1935-36, while on leave from MIT. During World War II he
    developed improvements in radar and Navy projectiles and devised
    a method of solving problems of fire control.
    In the years after World War II Wiener worked with the Mexican
    physiologist Arturo Rosenblueth on problems in biology, and
    formulated the set of ideas spanning several disciplines which came
    to be known as ‘cybernetics’. He worked with engineers and
    medical doctors to develop devices that could replace a lost sensory
    mode. He analysed some non-linear mathematical problems and,
    with Armand Siegel, reformulated quantum theory as a stochastic
    process. He also became an articulate commentator on the social
    implications of science and technology. In 1964 Wiener was
    recipient of the US National Medal of Science.
    His published works include The Fourier Integral a11d Cettain ofIts
    Applications (1933); Cybemetics (1948); Extrapolation and Interpolation
    and Smoothing of Stationary Time Series with Engineering Applications
    (1949); the first volume of an autobiography, Ex-Prodigy: My
    Childhood and Youth (1953); Tempter (1959); and Cod and Colem
    (1964). Wiener’s published articles have been assembled and edited
    by P. Masani and republished in four volumes as Norbert Utlener:
    Collected Works (1985).
    STEVE J. HEIMS received his doctorate in physics from Stanford
    University, California. He engaged in research in the branch of
    X
    THE HuMAN UsE or HuMAN BEINGS
    physics known as statistical mechanics and taught at several North
    American universities. In recent years he has devoted himself to
    studying various contexts of scientific work: social, philosophical,
    political and technological. He is the author of John von Neumann
    and Norbert Wiener: From Mathematics to the Technologies of Life and
    Death (MIT Press, 1980). Currently he is writing a book dealing
    with the characteristics of social studies in the USA during the
    decade following World War II.
    INTRODUCTION
    Steve J. Heims
    G.H. Hardy, the Cambridge mathematician and author of
    A Mathematicians Apology, reflecting on the value of
    mathematics, insisted that it is a ‘harmless and innocent
    occupation’. ‘Real mathematics has no effects on war’, he
    explained in a book for the general public in 1940. ‘No one
    has yet discovered any warlike purpose to be served by the
    theory of numbers or relativity … A real mathematician has
    his conscience clear.’ Yet, in fact, at that time physicists were
    already actively engaged in experiments converting matter
    into energy (a possibility implied by the Theory of Relativity)
    in anticipation of building an atomic bomb. Of the younger
    generation which he taught, Hardy wrote, ‘I have helped to
    train other mathematicians, but mathematicians of the same
    kind as myself, and their work has been, so far at any rate as I
    have helped them to it, as useless as my own … ‘
    Norbert Wiener took issue with his mentor. He thought
    Hardy’s attitude to be ‘pure escapism’, noted that the ideas of
    number theory are applied in electrical engineering, and that
    ‘no matter how innocent he may be in his inner soul and in
    his motivation, the effective mathematician is likely to be a
    powerful factor in changing the face of society. Thus he is
    really as dangerous as a potential armourer of the new
    scientific war of the future.’ The neat separation of pure and
    applied mathematics is only a mathematician’s self-serving
    illusion.
    Wiener came to address the alternative to innocence namely, taking responsibility. After he himself had during
    World War II worked on a mathematical theory of prediction
    intended to enhance the effectiveness of anti-aircraft fire, and
    developed a powerful statistical theory of communication
    which would put modern communication engineering on a
    rigorous mathematical footing, any pretence of harmlessness
    was out of the question for him. From the time of the end of
    the war until his death in 1964, Wiener applied his
    xii
    THE HUMAN UsE OF HuMAN BEINGS
    penetrating and innovative mind to identifying and elaborating on a relation of high technology to people which is benign
    or, in his words, to the human – rather than the inhuman use of human beings. In doing so during the years when the
    cold war was raging in the United States, he found an
    audience among the generally educated public. However,
    most of his scientifi.c colleagues- offended or embarrassed by
    Wiener1s views and especially by his open refusal to engage in
    any more work related to the military – saw him as an
    eccentric at best and certainly not to be taken seriously except
    in his undeniably brilliant, strictly mathematical, researches.
    Albert Einstein, who regarded Wiener’s attitude towards the
    military as exemplary, was in those days similarly made light
    of as unschooled in political matters.
    Undaunted, Wiener proceeded to construct a practical and
    comprehensive attitude towards technology rooted in his
    basic philosophical outlook, and presented it in lucid
    language. For him technologies were viewed not so much as
    applied science, but rather as applied social and moral
    philosophy. Others have been critical of technological
    developments and seen the industrial revolution as a mixed
    blessing. Unlike most of these critics, Wiener was simultaneously an irrepressibly original non-stop thinker in
    mathematics, the sciences and high technology and equally an
    imaginative critic from a social, historical and ethical
    perspective of the uses of his own and his colleagues,
    handiwork. Because he gave rather unchecked rein to both of
    these inclinations, Wiener1s writings generate a particular
    tension and have a special fascination.
    Now, four decades later, we see that the tenor of his
    comments on science, technology and society were on the
    whole prophetic and ahead of his time. In the intervening
    years his subject matter, arising out of the tension between
    technical fascination and social conscience, has become a
    respectable topic for research and scholarship. Even leading
    universities have caught up with it and created courses of
    study and academic departments with names such as ‘science
    studies,, ‘technology studies, or ‘science, technology and
    INTRODUCTION
    xiii
    society’. His prediction of an imminent ‘communication
    revolution’ in which ‘the message’ would be a pivotal notion,
    and the associated technological developments would be in
    the area of communication, computation and organization,
    was dear-sighted indeed.
    The interrelation between science and society via technologies is only one of the two themes underlying The Human
    Use of Human Beings. The other derives as much from
    Wiener’s personal philosophy as from theoretical physics.
    Although he was a mathematician, his personal philosophy
    was rooted in existentialism, rather than in the formal-logical
    analytical philosophy so prominent in his day and associated
    with the names of Russell, Moore, Ramsey, Wittgenstein and
    Ayer. For Wiener life entailed struggle, but it was not the
    class struggle as a means to social progress emphasized by
    Marxists, nor was it identical with the conflict Freud saw
    between the individual and society. In his own words:
    We are swimming upstream against a great torrent of disorganization, which tends to reduce everything to the heat death of
    equilibrium and sameness described in the second law of thermodynamics. What Maxwell, Bolzmann and Gibbs meant by this heat
    death in physics has a counterpart in the ethic of Kierkegaard, who
    pointed out that we live in a chaotic moral universe. In this, our
    main obligation is to establish arbitrary enclaves of order and
    system. These enclaves will not remain there indefinitely by any
    momentum of their own after we have once established them …
    We arc not fighting for a definitive victory in the indefinite future. It
    is the greatest possible victory to be, to continue to be, and to have
    been … This is no defeatism, it is rather a sense of tragedy in a
    world in which necessity is represented by an inevitable disappearance of differentiation. The declaration of our own nature and the
    attempt to build an enclave of organization in the face of nature’s
    overwhelming tendency to disorder is an insolence against the gods
    and the iron necessity that they impose. Here lies tragedy, but here
    lies glory too.
    Even when we discount the romantic, heroic overtones in that
    statement, Wiener is articulating what, as he saw and
    experienced it, makes living meaningful. The adjective
    ‘arbitrary’ before ‘order and system’ helps to make the
    xtv
    THE HUMAN UsE OF HuMAt\. BEINGS
    statement appropriate for many; it might have been made by
    an artist as readily as by a creative scientist. Wiener’s outlook
    on life is couched in the language of conflict and heroic
    struggle against overwhelming natural tendencies. But he was
    talking about something very different from the ruthless
    exploitation, even destruction, of nature and successfully
    bending it to human purposes, which is part of the legacy,
    part of the nineteenth-century heroic ideal, of Western man.
    Wiener in his discussion of human purposes, recognizing
    feedbacks and larger systems which include the environment,
    had moved far away from that ideal and closer to an ideal of
    understanding and, both consciously and effectively, of
    collaborating with natural processes.
    I expect that Wiener would have welcomed some more
    recent developments in physics, as his thinking was already at
    times tending in that direction. Since his day developments in
    the field of statistical mechanics have come to modify the
    ideas about how orderly patterns- for example, the growth of
    plants and animals and the evolution of ecosystems – arise in
    the face of the second law of thermodynamics. As Wiener
    anticipated, the notions of information, feedback and nonlinearity of the differential equations have become increasingly important in biology.
    But beyond that, Ilya Prigogine and his co-workers in
    Belgium have more recently made a convincing case that
    natural systems which are either far from thermodynamic
    equilibrium initially, or which fluctuate, may not return to
    equilibrium at all (G. Nicolis and I. Prigogine, SelfOrganization in No11equilibrium Systems, 1977). Instead they
    continue to move still further away from equilibrium towards
    a different, increasingly complex and orderly, but nevertheless stable pattern -not necessarily static, but possibly cyclic.
    According to the American physicist Willard Gibbs’ way of
    thinking, the stable state of a system – equilibrium – is
    independent of its detailed initial conditions, yet that
    simplification ·no longer holds for systems finding stability far
    from equilibrium. This is an explicit mechanism quite
    different from that of a ‘Maxwell demon’ (explained in
    INTRODUCTION
    XV
    Chapter 2), the mechanism assumed necessary in Wiener’s
    day. It is more nearly related to Wiener’s notion of positive
    feedback, which he tended to see as only disruptive and
    destructive, rather than as leading to complex stable structures. The results obtained by the Prigogine group show the
    creation of orderly patterns – natural countertrends to the
    tendency towards disorganization – to be stronger and more
    ordinary and commonplace than a sole reliance on mechanisms of the Maxwell-demon type would suggest. Sensitivity to
    initial conditions is also a prominent feature of ‘chaos theory’,
    currently an active field of research.
    If, however, we now extend Wiener’s analogy from
    statistical mechanics and incorporate the findings of the
    Prigogine group – according to which natural and spontaneous mechanisms other than just the Maxwell demon
    generate organization and differentiation – this suggests a
    shift in emphasis from ‘the human fight against the increase
    of entropy to create local enclaves of order’ to a more
    co-operative endeavour which to a considerable extent occurs
    naturally and of its own accord. It is a subtle shift that can,
    however, make large differences. Yet to be explored, these
    differences appear to echo disagreements that some modern
    feminists, neo-Taoists and ecologists have with classical
    Greek concepts of the heroic and the tragic.
    Wiener’s status, which he strongly prized, was that of an
    independent scientifically knowledgeable intellectual. He
    avoided accepting funds from government agencies or
    corporations that might in any way compromise his complete
    honesty and independence. Nor did he identify himself with
    any political, social or philosophical group, but spoke and
    wrote simply as an individual. He was suspicious of honours
    and prizes given for scientific achievement. After receiving
    the accolade of election to the National Academy of Sciences,
    he. resigned, lest membership in that select, exclusive body of
    sclentists corrupt his autonomous status as outsider vis-a-vis
    the American scientific establishment He was of the tradition
    in which it is the intellectual’s respon~ibility to speak truth to
    power. This was in the post-war years, when the US
    XVI
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    government and many scientists and science administrators
    were celebrating the continuing partnership between government and science, government providing the funds and
    scientists engaging in research. Wiener remained aloof and
    highly critical of that peacetime arrangement. More precisely,
    he tried to stay aloof, but he would not separate himself
    completely because for many years he remained a professor at
    the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, an institution
    heavily involved in that partnership. As was his nature, he
    continued to talk to colleagues about his own fertile ideas,
    whether they dealt with mathematics, engineering or social
    concerns.
    The Human Use of Human Beings, first published in 1950,
    was a sequel to an earlier volume, Cybernetics: Or Control and
    Communication in the Animal and the Machine. That earlier
    volume broke new ground in several respects. First of all, it
    was a report on new scientific and technical developments of
    the 1940s, especially on information theory, communication
    theory and communications technology, models of the brain
    and general-purpose computers. Secondly, it extended ideas
    and used metaphors from physics and electrical engineering
    to discuss a variety of topics including neuropathology,
    politics, society, learning and the nature of time.
    Wiener had been an active participant in pre-war interdisciplinary seminars. After the war he regularly took part in a
    series of small conferences of mathematicians and engineers,
    which were also attended by biologists, anthropologists,
    sociologists, psychologists and psychiatrists, in which the set
    of ideas subsumed under cybernetics was explored in the
    light of these various disciplines. At these conferences
    Wiener availed himself of the convenient opportunity to
    become acquainted with current research on a broad range of
    topics outside of his speciality.
    Already in his Cybernetics Wiener had raised questions
    about the benefits of the new ideas and technologies,
    concluding pessimistically,
    there are those who hope that the good of a better understanding of
    INTRODUCTION
    xvii
    man and society which is offered by this new field of work may
    anticipate and outweigh the incidental contribution we arc making
    to the concentration of power. I write in 1947, and I am compelled
    to say that it is a very slight hope.
    The book was a rarity also in that, along with the technical
    material, he discussed ethical issues at length. The Human Use
    ofHuman Beings is a popularization of Cybernetics (omitting the
    forbidding mathematics), though with a special emphasis on
    the description of the human and the social.
    The present volume is a reprint of the second (1954)
    edition, which differs signifi.cantly from the original hardcover edition. The notable reorganization of the book and the
    changes made deserve attention. In the first edition we read
    that ‘the purpose of this book is both to explain the
    potentialities of the machine in fields which up to now have
    been taken to be purely human, and to warn against the
    dangers of a purely selfish exploitation of these possibilities in
    a world in which to human beings human things are
    all-important.’ After commenting critically about patterns of
    social organization in which all orders come from above, and
    none return (‘an ideal held by many Fascists, Strong Men in
    Business, and Governmenf), he explains, ‘I wish to devote
    this book [fi.rst edition] to a protest against this inhuman use
    of human beings! The second edition, in contrast, as stated
    in the Preface, is organized around Wiener’s other major
    theme, ‘the impact of the Gibbs ian point of view on modern
    life, both through the substantive changes it has made in
    working science, and through the changes it has made
    indirectly in our attitude to life in general.’ The second
    edition, where the framework is more philosophical and less
    political, appears to be presented in such a way as to make it
    of interest not only in 1954, but also for many years to come.
    The writing and the organization are a bit tighter and more
    orderly than in the first edition. It also includes comment on
    some exemplifications of cybernetics (e.g., the work of Ross
    Ashby) that had come to Wiener’s attention only during the
    early 1950s. Yet, even though several chapters are essentially
    unchanged, something was lost in going from the first to the
    xvm
    THE HUMAN UsE OF HUMAN BEINGs
    second edition. I miss the bluntness and pungency of some of
    the comments in the earlier edition, which apparently were
    ‘cleaned up’ for the second.
    The cause celebre in 1954 in the USA was the Oppenheimer
    case. J. Robert Oppenheimer, the physicist who had directed
    the building of atom bombs during World War II, had
    subsequently come to disagree with the politically dominant
    figures in the government who were eager to develop and
    build with the greatest possible speed hydrogen bombs a
    thousand times more powerful than the atom bombs which
    had devastated Hiroshima and Nagasaki. Oppenheimer
    urged delay, as he preferred that a further effort be made to
    negotiate with the Soviet Union before proceeding with such
    an irreversible escalation of the arms race. This policy
    difference lay behind the dramatic Oppenheimer hearings,
    humiliating proceedings at the height of the anti-Communist
    ‘McCarthy era’ (and of the US Congressional ‘On-American
    Activities Committee’), leading to, absurdly, the labelling of
    Oppenheimer as a ‘security risk’.
    In that political atmosphere it is not surprising for a
    publisher to prefer a different focus than the misuse of the
    latest technologies, or the dangers of capitalist exploitation of
    technologies for profit. Wiener himself was at that time going
    on a lecture tour to India and was then occupied with several
    other projects, such as writing the second volume of his
    autobiography, the mathematical analysis of brain waves,
    sensory prosthesis and a new formulation of quantum theory.
    He did not concern himself a great deal with the revision of a
    book he had written several years earlier – it would be more
    characteristic of him to write a new book or add a new
    chapter, rather than revise a book already written- although
    he must have agreed to all revisions and editorial changes.
    At the end of the book, in both editions, Wiener compares
    the Catholic Church with the Communist Party, and both
    with cold war government activities in capitalist America. The
    criticisms of America in these last few pages of the first
    edition (see Appendix to this Introduction) are, in spite of one
    brief pointed reference to McCarthyism, largely absent in the
    INTRODUCTION
    XIX
    second edition. There are other differences in the two
    editions. The chapter ‘Progress and Entropy’, for example, is
    much longer in the first edition. The section on the history of
    inventions within that chapter is more detailed. The chapter
    also deals with such topics as the depletion of resources and
    American dependence on other nations for oil, copper and
    tin, and the possibility of an energy-crisis unless new
    inventions obviate it. It reviews vividly the progress in
    medicine and anticipates new problems, such as the increasing use of synthetic foods that may contain minute quantities
    of carcinogens. These and other discursive excursions,
    peripheral to the main line of argument of the book, are
    omitted in the present edition.
    The Human Use ofHuman Beings was not Wiener’s last word
    on the subject. He continued to think and talk and write. In
    1959 he addressed and provoked a gathering of scientists by
    his reflections and analysis of some moral and technical
    consequences of automation (Science, vol. 131, p. 1358,
    1960), and in his last book (God and Go/em, Inc., 1964) he
    returned to ethical concerns from the perspective of the
    creative scientist or engineer.
    It was Wiener’s lifelong obsession to distinguish the human
    from the machine, having recognized the identity of patterns
    of organization and of many functions which can be
    performed by either, but in The Human Use ofHuman Beings it
    is his intention to place his understanding of the people/
    machines identity/dichotomy within the context of his
    generous and humane social philosophy. Cybernetics had
    originated from the analysis of formal analogies between the
    behaviour of organisms and that of electronic and mechanical
    systems. The mostly military technologies new in his day,
    which today we call ‘artificial intelligence’, highlighted the
    potential resemblance between certain elaborate machines
    and people. Academic psychology in North America was in
    those days still predominantly behaviourist. The cybernetic
    machines -such as general-purpose computers- suggested a
    possibility as to the nature of mind: mind was analogous to
    the formal structure and organization, or the software aspect,
    XX
    THE HUMAN UsE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    of a reasoning-and-perceiving machine that could also issue
    instructions leading to actions. Thus the long-standing
    mind-brain duality was overcome by a materialism which
    encompassed organization, messages and information in
    addition to stuff and matter. But the subjective – an
    individual’s cumulative experience, sensations and feelings,
    including the subjective experience of being alive – is
    belittled, seen only within the context of evolutionary theory
    as providing information useful for survival to the organism.
    If shorn of Wiener’s benign social philosophy, what
    remains of cybernetics can be used within a highly mechanical and dehumanizing, even militaristic, outlook. The fact
    that the metaphor of a sophisticated automaton is so heavily
    employed invites thinking about humans as in effect
    machines. Many who have learned merely the technical
    aspects of cybernetics have used them, and do so today, for
    ends which Wiener abhorred. It is a danger he foresaw,
    would have liked to obviate and, although aware of how little
    he could do in that regard, valiantly tried to head off.
    The technological developments in themselves are impressive, but since most of us already have to bear with a glut
    of promotional literature it is more to the point here to frame
    discussion not in the promoters’ terms (what the new
    machine can do), but in a more human and social framework:
    how is the machine affecting people’s lives? Or still more
    pointedly: who reaps a benefit from it? Wiener urged
    scientists and engineers to practise ‘the imaginative forward
    glance’ so as to attempt assessing the impact of an innovation,
    even before making it known.
    However, once some of the machines or techniques were
    put on the market, a younger generation with sensitivity to
    human and social impacts could report empirically where the
    shoe pinches. Even though such reports may not suffice to
    radically change conventional patterns of deployment of
    technologies, which after all express many kinds of political
    and economic interests, they at least document what happens
    and help 😮 educate the public. As long as their authors avoid
    an a priori pro-technology or anti-technology bias, they
    INTRODUCTION
    effectively carry on where Wiener left off. Among such
    reports we note Joseph Weizenbaum’s description of the
    human damage manifested in the ‘compulsive programmer’,
    which poses questions about appropriate and inappropriate
    uses of computers (Computer Power and Human Reason, 1976).
    Similarly David Noble has documented how the introduction
    of automation in the machine-tool industry has resulted in a
    deskilling of machinists to their detriment, and has described
    in detail the political process by which this deskilling was
    brought about (Forces of Production, 1984).
    These kinds of’inhuman’ uses seem nearly subtle if placed
    next to the potentially most damaging use, war. The growth of
    communication-computation-automation devices and systems had made relatively small beginnings during World War
    II, but since then has been given high priority in US
    government-subsidized military research and development,
    and in the Soviet Union as well; their proliferation in military
    contexts has been enormous and extensive. A proper critique
    would entail an analysis in depth of world politics, and
    especially the political relations of the two ‘superpowers’.
    Wiener feared that he had helped to provide tools for the
    centralization of power, and indeed he and his fellow
    scientists and engineers had. For instance, under the Reagan
    government many billions of dollars were spent on plans for a
    protracted strategic nuclear war with the Soviet Union. The
    technological ‘challenge’ was seen to be the development of
    an effective C-cubed system (command, control and communication) which would be used to destroy enemy political
    and command centres and at the same time, through a
    multitude of methods, prevent the destruction of the
    corresponding American centres, leaving the USA fully in
    command throughout the nuclear war and victorious. Some
    principled scientists and engineers have, in a Wienerian
    spirit, refused to work on, or have stopped working on, such
    mad schemes, or on implementing the politicians’ ‘StarWars’ fantasies.
    We have already alluded to Wiener’s heavy use of
    metaphors from engineering to describe the human and the
    xxu
    THE HuMAN UsE OF HuMAN BEINGS
    social, and his neglect of the subjective experience. In the
    post-war years American sociologists, anthropologists, political scientists and psychologists tried harder than ever to be
    seen as ‘scientific’. They readily borrowed the engineers’
    idiom and many sought to learn from the engineers’ or
    mathematicians’ thinking. Continental European social
    thinkers were far more inclined to attend to the human
    subject and to make less optimistic claims about their
    scientific expertise, but it required another decade before
    European thought substantially influenced the positivistic or
    logical-empiricist predilections of the mainstream of American social scientists.
    A major development in academic psychology, prominent
    and well-funded today, relies strongly on the concept of
    information processing and models based on the computer. It
    traces its origins to the discussions on cybernetics in the
    post-war years and the wartime work of the British psychologist Kenneth Craik. This development, known as ‘cognitive
    science’, entirely ignores background contexts, the culture,
    the society, history, subjective experience, human feelings
    and emotions. Thus it works with a highly impoverished
    model of what it is to be human. Such models have, however,
    found their challengers and critics, ranging from the journalist Gordon Ratray Taylor (The Natural History ofMind, 1979)
    to the psychologist James]. Gibson, the latter providing a far
    different approach to how humans know and perceive (The
    Perception of the Visual World, 1950; The Senses Considered as
    Perceptual Systems, 1966; The Ecological Approach to Visual
    Perception, 1979).
    If we trace the intellectual history of current thinking in
    such diverse fields as cellular biology, medicine, anthropology, psychiatry, ecology and economics, we find that in each
    discipline concepts coming from cybernetics consitute one of
    the streams that have fed it. Cybernetics, including information theory, systems with purposive behaviour and automaton
    models, was part of the intellectual dialogue of the 1950s and
    has since mingled with many other streams, has been absorbed
    and become part of the conventional idiom and practice.
    INTRODUCTION
    xxiii
    Too many writings about technologies are dismal, narrow
    apologetics for special interests, and not very edifying. Yet the
    subject matter is intrinsically extremely varied and stimulating
    to an enquiring mind. It has profound implications for our
    day-to-day lives, their structure and their quality. The social
    history of science and technology is a rich resource, even for
    imagining and reflecting on the future. Moreover the topic
    highlights central dilemmas in every political system. For
    example, how is the role of ‘experts’ in advising governments
    related to political process? Or how is it possible to reconcile,
    in a capitalist economy within a democratic political structure,
    the unavoidable conflict between public interest and decision
    by a popular vote, on the one hand, and corporate decisions
    as to which engineering projects are profitable, on the other?
    We are now seeing the rise of a relatively new genre of
    writing about technologies and people which is interesting,
    concrete, open, exploratory and confronts political issues
    head-on. We need this writing, for we are living in what Ellul
    has appropriately called a technological society. Within that
    genre, Wiener’s books, as well as some earlier writings by
    Lewis Mumford, are among the few pioneering works that
    have become classics. The present reissue of one of these
    classics is cause for rejoicing. May it stimulate readers to
    think passionately for themselves about the human use of
    human beings with the kind of intellectual honesty and
    compassion Wiener brought to the subject.
    Steve J. Heims
    Boston, October 1988
    APPENDIX
    What follows are two documents from Norbert Wiener’s
    writings:
    -an open letter published in the Atlantic Monthly magazine,
    January 1947 issue; and
    -the concluding passages of The Human Use ofHuman Beings,
    lst edition, Houghton-Mifflin, 1950, pp. 228-9.
    XXVI
    THE HuMAN UsE OF HuMAN BEINGS
    A Scu.NTisT RHRF.t.s
    The letter which follows was addressed by one of our
    ranking mathematicians to a research scientist of a great
    aircraft corporation, who had asked him for the technical
    account of a certain line of research he had conducted in the
    war. Professor Wiener’s indignation at being requested to
    participate in indiscriminate rearmament, less than two years
    after victory, is typical of many American scientists who
    served their country faithfully during the war.
    Professor of Mathematics in one of our great Eastern
    institutions, Norbert Wiener was born in Columbia, Missouri, in 1894, the son of Leo Wiener, Professor of Slavic
    Languages at Harvard University. He took his doctorate at
    Harvard and did his graduate work in England and in
    Gottingen. Today he is esteemed one of the world’s foremost
    mathematical analysts. His ideas played a significant part in
    the development of the theories of communication and
    control which were essential in winning the war.
    -The Editor, Atlantic Monthly
    Sir:I have received from you a note in which you state that you
    are engaged in a project concerning controlled missiles, and
    in which you request a copy of a paper which I wrote for the
    National Defense Research Committee during the war.
    As the paper is the property of a government organization,
    you are of course at complete liberty to turn to that government organization for such information as I could give you. If
    it is out of print as you say, and they desire to make it available
    for you, there are doubtless proper avenues of approach to
    them.
    When, however, you turn to me for information concerning
    controlled missiles, there are several considerations which
    determine my reply. In the past, the comity of scholars has
    made it a custom to furnish scientific information to any
    person seriously seeking it. However, we must face these
    facts: the policy of the government itself during and after the
    APPENDIX
    XA’Vii
    war, say in the bombing of Hiroshima and Nagasaki, has
    made it clear that to provide scientific information is not a
    necessarily innocent act, and may entail the gravest consequences. One therefore cannot escape reconsidering the established custom of the scientist to give information to every
    person who may enquire of him. The interchange of ideas
    which is one of the great traditions of science must of course
    receive certain limitations when the scientist becomes an
    arbiter of life and death.
    For the sake, however, of the scientist and the public, these
    limitations should be as intelligent as possiple. The measures
    taken during the war by our military agencies, in restricting
    the free intercourse among scientists on related projects or
    even on the same project, have gone so far that it is clear that
    if continued in time of peace this policy will lead to the total
    irresponsibility of the scientist, and ultimately to the death of
    science. Both of these are disastrous for our ci¥ilization, and
    entail grave and immediate peril for the public.
    I realize, of course, that I am acting as the censor of my
    own ideas, and it may sound arbitrary, but I will not accept a
    censorship in which I do not participate. The experience of
    the scientists who have worked on the atomic bomb has
    indicated that in any investigation of this kind the scientist
    ends by putting unlimited powers in the hands of the people
    whom he is least inclined to trust with their use. It is perfectly
    clear also that to disseminate information about a weapon in
    the present state of our civilization is to make it practically
    certain that that weapon will be used. In that respect the
    controlled missile represents the still imperfect supplement to
    the atom bomb and to bacterial warfare.
    The practical use of guided missiles can only be to kill
    foreign civilians indiscriminately, and it furnishes no protection whatsoever to civilians in this country. I cannot conceive
    a situation in which such weapons can produce any effect
    other than extending the kamikaze way of fighting to whole
    nations. Their possession can do nothing but endanger us by
    encouraging the tragic insolence of the military mind.
    If therefore I do not desire to participate in the bombing or
    xxviii
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    poisoning of defenceless peoples- and I most certainly do not
    – I must take a serious responsibility as to those to whom I
    disclose my scientific ideas. Since it is obvious that with
    sufficient effort you can obtain my material, even though it is
    out of print, I can only protest pro fonna in refusing to give you
    any information concerning my past work. However, I rejoice
    at the fact that my material is not readily available, inasmuch
    as it gives me the opportunity to raise this serious moral issue.
    I do not expect to publish any future work of mine which may
    do damage in the hands of irresponsible militarists.
    I am taking the liberty of calling this letter to the attention
    of other people in scientific work. I believe it is only proper
    that they should know of it in order to make their own
    independent decisions, if similar situations should confront
    them.
    Norbert Wiener
    APPENDIX
    xxix
    THE: HUMAN UsE OF HvM.-IN BnNcs
    I have indicated that freedom of opinion at the present time
    is being crushed between the two rigidities of the Church and
    the Communist Party. In the United States we are in the
    process of developing a new rigidity which combines the
    methods of both while partaking of the emotional fervour of
    neither. Our Conservatives of all shades of opinion have
    somehow got together to make American capitalism and the
    fifth freedom of the businessman supreme throughout all the
    world.
    Our military men and our great merchant princes have
    looked upon the propaganda technique of the Russians, and
    have found that it is good. They have found a worthy
    counterpart for the GPU in the FBI, in its new role of
    political censor. They have not considered that these
    weapons form something fundamentally distasteful to
    humanity, and that they need the full force of an overwhelming faith and belief to make them even tolerable. This faith
    and belief they have nowhere striven to replace. Thus they
    have been false to the dearest part of our American traditions,
    without offering us any principles for which we may die,
    eXcept a merely negative hatred of Communism. They have
    succeeded in being un-American without being radical. To
    this end we have invented a new inquisition: the Inquisition of
    Teachers’ Oaths and of Congressional Committees. We have
    synthesized a new propaganda, lacking only one element
    which is common to the Church and to the Communist Party,
    and that is the element of Belief. We have accepted the
    methods, not the ideals of our possible antagonists, little
    realizing that it is the ideals which have given the methods
    whatever cogency they possess. Ourselves without faith, we
    presume to punish heresy. May the absurdity of our position
    soon perish amidst the Homeric laughter that it deserves.
    It is this triple attack on our liberties which we must resist,
    if communication is to have the scope that it properly
    deserves as the central phenomenon of society, and if the
    human individual is to reach and to maintain his full stature.
    XXX
    THE HuMAN UsE oF HuMAN BEINGS
    It is again the American worship of know-how as opposed to
    know-what that hampers us. We rightly see great dangers in
    the totalitarian system of Communism. On the one hand, we
    have called in to combat these the assistance of a totalitarian
    Church which is in no respect ready to accept, in support of
    its standards, milder means than those to which Communism
    appeals. On the other hand, we have attempted to synthesize
    a rigid system to fight fire by fire, and to oppose Communism
    by institutions which bear more than a fortuitous resemblance
    to Communistic institutions. In this we have failed to realize
    that the element in Communism which essentially deserves
    our respect consists in its loyalties and in its insistence on the
    dignity and the rights of the worker. What is bad consists
    chiefly in the ruthless techniques to which the present phase
    of the Communist revolution has resorted. Our leaders show
    a disquieting complacency in their acceptance of the ruthlessness and a disquieting unwillingness to refer their acts to any
    guiding principles. Fundamentally, behind our counterruthlessness there is no adequate basis of real heartfelt
    assent. Let us hope that it is still possible to reverse the tide of
    the moment and to create a future America in which man can
    live and can grow to be a human being in the fullest and
    richest sense of the word.
    PREFACE
    THE IDEA OF A CONTINGENT UNNERSE
    The beginning of the twentieth century marked
    more than the end of one hundred-year period and the
    start of another. There was a real change of point of
    view even before we made the political transition from
    the century on the whole dominated by peace, to the
    half century of war through which we have just been
    living. This was perhaps first apparent in science, although it is quite possible that whatever has affected
    science led independently to the marked break which
    we find between the arts and literature of the nineteenth and those of the twentieth centuries.
    Newtonian physics, which had ruled from the end of
    the seventeenth century to the end of the nineteenth
    with scarcely an opposing voice, described a universe
    in which everything happened precisely according to
    law, a compact, tightly organized universe in which the
    whole future depends strictly upon the whole past.
    Such a picture can never be either fully justified or
    fully rejected experimentally and belongs in large
    measure to a conception of the world which is supplementary to experiment but in some ways more universal than anything that can be experimentally
    verified. We can never test by our imperfect experiments whether one set of physical laws or another can
    be verified down to the last decimal. The Newtonian
    view, however, was compelled to state and formulate
    physics as if it were, in fact, subject to such laws. This
    is now no longer the dominating attitude of physics,
    and the men who contributed most to its downfall were
    Bolzmann in Germany and Gibbs in the United States.
    These two physicists undertook a radical application
    of an exciting, new idea. Perhaps the use of statistics
    in physics which, in large measure, they introduced
    was not completely new, for Maxwell and others had
    8
    TilE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    considered worlds of very large numbers of particles
    which necessarily had to be treated statistically. But
    what Holzmann and Gibbs did was to introduce statistics into physics in a much more thoroughgoing way,
    so that the statistical approach was valid not merely
    for systems of enormous complexity, but even for systems as simple as the single particle in a field of force.
    Statistics is the science of distribution, and the distribution contemplated by these modern scientists was
    not concerned with large numbers of similar particles,
    but with the various positions and velocities from
    which a physical system might start. In other words,
    under the Newtonian system the same physical laws
    apply to a variety of systems starting from a variety of
    positions and with a variety of momenta. The new statisticians put this point of view in a fresh light. They
    retained indeed the principle according to which certain systems may be distinguished from others by their
    total energy, but they rejected the supposition according to which systems with the same total energy may
    be clearly distinguished indefinitely and described forever by fixed causal laws.
    There was, actually, an important statistical reservation implicit in Newton’s work, though the eighteenth
    century, which lived by Newton, ignored it. No physical measurements are ever precise; and what we have
    to say about a machine or other dynamic system really
    concerns not what we must expect when the initial positions and momenta are given with perfect accuracy
    (which never occurs), but what we are to expect when
    they are given with attainable accuracy. This merely
    means that we know, not the complete initial conditions, but something about their distribution. The functional part of physics, in other words, cannot escape
    considering uncertainty and the contingency of events.
    It was the merit of Gibbs to show for the first time a
    clean-cut scientific method for taking this contingency
    into consideration.
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    9
    The historian of science looks in vain for a single line
    of development. Gibbs’ work, while well cut out, was
    badly sewed, and it remained for others to complete
    the job that he began. The intuition on which he based
    his work was that, in general, a physical system belonging to a class of physical systems, which continues to
    retain its identity as a class, eventually reproduces in
    almost all cases the distribution which it shows at any
    given time over the whole class of systems. In other
    words, under certain circumstances a system runs
    through all the distributions of position and momentum
    which are compatible with its energy, if it keeps running long enough.
    This last proposition, however, is neither true nor
    possible in anything but trivial systems. Nevertheless,
    there is another route leading to the results which
    Gibbs needed to bolster his hypothesis. The irony of
    history is that this route was being explored very thoroughly in Paris at exactly the time when Gibbs was
    working in New Haven; and yet it was not until 1920
    that the Paris work met the New Haven work in a fruitful union. I had, I believe, the honor of assisting at the
    birth of the first child of this union.
    Gibbs had to work with theories of measure and
    probability which were already at least twenty-five
    years old and were grossly inadequate to his needs. At
    the same time, however, Borel and Lebesgue in Paris
    were devising the theory of integration which was to
    prove apposite to the Gibbsian ideas. Borel was a mathematician who had already made his reputation in the
    theory of probability and had an excellent physical
    sense. He did work leading to this theory of measure,
    but he did not reach the stage in which he could close
    it into a complete theory. This was done by his pupil
    Lebesgue, who was a very different sort of person. He
    had neither the sense of physics nor an interest in it.
    Nonetheless Lebesgue solved the problem put by
    Borel, but he regarded the solution of this problem as
    10
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    no more than a tool for Fourier series and other
    branches of pure mathematics. A quarrel developed
    between the two men when they both became candidates for admission to the French Academy of Sciences, and only after a great deal of mutual
    denigration, did they both receive this honor. Borel,
    however, continued to maintain the importance of
    Lebesgue’s work and his own as a physical tool; but I
    believe that I myself, in 1920, was the first person to
    apply the Lebesgue integral to a specific physical problem-that of the Brownian motion.
    This occurred long after Gibbs’ death, and his work
    remained for two decades one of those mysteries of science which work even though it seems that they ought
    not to work. Many men have had intuitions well ahead
    of their time; and this is not least true in mathematical
    physics. Gibbs’ introduction of probability into physics
    occurred well before there was an adequate theory of
    the sort of probability he needed. But for all these gaps
    it is, I am convinced, Gibbs rather than Einstein or
    Heisenberg or Planck to whom we must attribute the
    first great revolution of twentieth century physics.
    This revolution has had the effect that physics now
    no longer claims to deal with what will always happen,
    but rather with what will happen with an overwhelming probability. At the beginning in Gibbs’ own work
    this contingent attitude was superimposed on a Newtonian base in which the elements whose probability
    was to be discussed were systems obeying all of the
    Newtonian laws. Gibbs’ theory was essentially new,
    but the permutations with which it was compatible
    were the same as those contemplated by Newton.
    What has happened to physics since is that the rigid
    Newtonian basis has been discarded or modified, and
    the Gibbsian contingency now stands in its complete
    nakedness as the full basis of physics. It is true that
    the books are not yet quite closed on this issue and
    that Einstein and, in some of his phases, De Broglie,
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    11
    still contend that a rigid deterministic world is more
    acceptable than a contingent one; but these great scientists are fighting a rear-guard action against the overwhelming force of a younger generation.
    One interesting change that has taken place is that
    in a probabilistic world we no longer deal with quantities and statements which concern a specific, real universe as a whole but ask instead questions which may
    find their answers in a large number of similar universes. Thus chance has been admitted, not merely as
    a mathematical tool for physics, but as part of its warp
    and weft.
    This recognition of an element of incomplete determinism, almost an irrationality in the world, is in a
    certain way parallel to Freud’s admission of a deep irrational component in human conduct and thought. In
    the present world of political as well as intellectual
    confusion, there is a natural tendency to class Gibbs,
    Freud, and the proponents of the modern theory of
    probability together as representatives of a single tendency; yet I do not wish to press this point. The gap
    between the Gibbs-Lebesgue way of thinking and
    Freud’s intuitive but somewhat discursive method is
    too large. Yet in their recognition of a fundamental element of chance in the texture of the universe itself,
    these men are close to one another and close to the
    tradition of St. Augustine. For this random element,
    this organic incompleteness, is one which without too
    violent a :Sgure of speech we may consider evil; the
    negative evil which St. Augustine characterizes as incompleteness, rather than the positive malicious evil of
    the Manichaeans.
    This book is devoted to the impact of the Gibbsian
    point of view on modern life, both through the substantive changes it has made in working science, and
    through the changes it has made indirectly in our attitude to life in general Thus the following chapters
    contain an element of technical description as well as
    12
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    a philosophic component which concerns what we do
    and how we should react to the new world that confronts us.
    I repeat: Gibbs’ innovation was to consider not one
    world, but all the worlds which are possible answers to
    a limited set of questions concerning our environment.
    His central notion concerned the extent to which answers that we may give to questions about one set of
    worlds are probable among a larger set of worlds. Beyond this, Gibbs had a theory that this probability
    tended naturally to increase as the universe grows
    older. The measure of this probability is called entropy,
    and the characteristic tendency of entropy is to increase.
    As entropy increases, the universe, and all closed
    systems in the universe, tend naturally to deteriorate
    and lose their distinctiveness, to move from the least
    to the most probable state, from a state of organization
    and differentiation in which distinctions and forms exist, to a state of chaos and sameness. In Gibbs’ universe
    order is least probable, chaos most probable. But while
    the universe as a whole, if indeed there is a whole universe, tends to run down, there are local enclaves
    whose direction seems opposed to that of the universe
    at large and in which there is a limited and temporary
    tendency .for organization to increase. Life finds its
    home in some of these enclaves. It is with this point of
    view at its core that the new science of Cybernetics
    began its development. 1
    1 There are those who are skeptical as to the precise
    identity between entropy and biological disorganization. It
    will be necessary for me to evaluate these criticisms sooner
    or later, but for the present I must assume that the differences lie, not in the fundamental nature of these quantities,
    but in the systems in which they are observed. It is too
    much to expect a final, clear~cut definition of entropy on
    which all writers will agree in any less than the closed,
    isolated system.
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    I
    CYBERNETICS IN HISTORY
    Since the end of World War II, I have been working
    on the many ramifications of the theory of messages.
    Besides the electrical engineering theory of the transmission of messages, there is a larger field which includes not only the study of language but the study of
    messages as a means of controlling machinery and
    society, the development of computing machines and
    other such automata, certain reflections upon psychology and the nervous system, and a tentative new theory
    of scientific method. This larger theory of messages is
    a probabilistic theory, an intrinsic part of the movement that owes its origin to Willard Gibbs and which
    I have described in the introduction.
    Until recently, there was no existing word for this
    complex of ideas, and in order to embrace the whole
    field by a single term, I felt constrained to invent one.
    Hence “Cybernetics,” which I derived from the Greek
    word kubemetes, or “steersman,” the same Greek word
    from which we eventually derive our word “governor.”
    Incidentally, I found later that the word had already
    been used by Ampere with reference to political
    science, and had been introduced in another context
    by a Polish scientist, both uses dating from the earlier
    part of the nineteenth century.
    I wrote a more or less technical book entitled
    Cybernetics which was published in 1948. In response
    to a certain demand for me to make its ideas acceptable
    to the lay public, I published the first edition of The
    Human Use of Human Beings in 1950. Since then the
    16
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    subject has grown from a few ideas shared by Drs.
    Claude Shannon, Warren Weaver, and myself, into an
    established region of research. Therefore, I take this
    opportunity occasioned by the reprinting of my book
    to bring it up to date, and to remove certain defects
    and inconsequentialities in its original structure.
    In giving the definition of Cybernetics in the original
    book, I classed communication and control together.
    Why did I do this? When I communicate with another
    person, I impart a message to him, and when he communicates back with me he returns a related message
    which contains information primarily accessible to him
    and not to me. When I control the actions of another
    person, I communicate a message to him, and although
    this message is in the imperative mood, the technique
    of communication does not differ from that of a message
    of fact. Furthermore, if my control is to be effective I
    must take cognizance of any messages from him which
    may indicate that the order is understood and has been
    obeyed.
    It is the thesis of this book that society can only be
    understood through a study of the messages and the
    communication facilities which belong to it; and that
    in the future development of these messages and communication facilities, messages between man and machines, between machines and man, and between
    machine and machine, are destined to play an everincreasing part.
    When I give an order to a machine, the situation is
    not essentially different from that which arises when
    I give an order to a person. In other words, as far as my
    consciousness goes I am aware of the order that has
    gone out and of the signal of compliance that has come
    back. To me, personally, the fact that the signal in its
    intermediate stages has gone through a machine rather
    than through a person is irrelevant and does not in any
    case greatly change my relation to the signal. Thus the
    theory of control in engineering, whether human or
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    animal or mechanical, is a chapter in the theory of
    messages.
    Naturally there are detailed differences in messages
    and in problems of control, not only between a living
    organism and a machine, but within each narrower
    class of beings. It is the purpose of Cybernetics to develop a language and techniques that will enable us
    indeed to attack the problem of control and communication in general, but also to find the proper repertory
    of ideas and techniques to classify their particular
    manifestations under certain concepts.
    The commands through which we exercise our control over our environment are a kind of information
    which we impart to it. Like any form of information,
    these commands are subject to disorganization in
    transit. They generally come through in less coherent
    fashion and certainly not more coherently than they
    were sent. In control and communication we are always
    fighting nature’s tendency to degrade the organized
    and to destroy the meaningful; the tendency, as Gibbs
    has shown us, for entropy to increase.
    Much of this book concerns the limits of communication within and among individuals. Man is immersed
    in a world which he perceives through his sense organs.
    Information that he receives is co-ordinated through
    his brain and nervous system until, after the proper
    process of storage, collation, and selection, it emerges
    through effector organs, generally his muscles. These
    in turn act on the external world, and also react on the
    central nervous system through receptor organs such
    as the end organs of kinaesthesia; and the information
    received by the kinaesthetic organs is combined with
    his already accumulated store of information to influence future action.
    Information is a name for the content of what is
    exchanged with the outer world as we adjust to it,
    and make our adjustment felt upon it. The process of
    receiving and of using information is the process of
    18
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    our adjusting to the contingencies of the outer environment, and of our living effectively within that environment. The needs and the complexity of modern life
    make greater demands on this process of information
    than ever before, and our press, our museums, our
    scientific laboratories, our universities, our libraries and
    textbooks, are obliged to meet the needs of this process
    or fail in their purpose. To live effectively is to live
    with adequate information. Thus, communication and
    control belong to the essence of man’s inner life, even
    as they belong to his life in society.
    The place of the study of communication in the history of science is neither trivial, fortuitous, nor new.
    Even before Newton such problems were current in
    physics, especially in the work of Fermat, Huygens,
    and Leibnitz, each of whom shared an interest in
    physics whose focus was not mechanics but optics, the
    communication of visual images.
    Fermat furthered the study of optics with his principle of minimization which says that over any sufficiently short part of its course, light follows the path
    which it takes the least time to traverse. Huygens developed the primitive form of what is now known as
    “Huygens’ Principle” by saying that light spreads from
    a source by forming around that source something like
    a small sphere consisting of secondary sources which
    in turn propagate light just as the primary sources do.
    Leibnitz, in the meantime, saw the whole world as a
    collection of beings called “monads” whose activity
    consisted in the perception of one another on the basis
    of a pre-established harmony laid down by God, and it
    is fairly clear that he thought of this interaction largely
    in optical terms. Apart from this perception, the monads had no “windows,” so that in his view all mechanical interaction really becomes nothing more than a
    subtle consequence of optical interaction.
    A preoccupation with optics and with message,
    which is apparent in this part of Leibnitz’s philosophy,
    19
    runs through its whole texture. It plays a large part in
    two of his most original ideas: that of the Characteristica Universalis, or universal scientific language, and
    that of the Calculus Ratiocinator, or calculus of logic.
    This Calculus Ratiocinator, imperfect as it was, was
    the direct ancestor of modern mathematical logic.
    Leibnitz, dominated by ideas of communication, is,
    in more than one way, the intellectual ancestor of the
    ideas of this book, for he was also interested in machine
    computation and in automata. My views in this book are
    very far from being Leibnitzian, but the problems with
    which I am concerned are most certainly Leibnitzian.
    Leibnitz’s computing machines were only an offshoot
    of his interest in a computing language, a reasoning
    calculus which again was in his mind, merely an extention of his idea of a complete artificial language.
    Thus, even in his computing machine, Leibnitz’s preoccupations were mostly linguistic and communicational.
    Toward the middle of the last century, the work of
    Clerk Maxwell and of his precursor, Faraday, had attracted the attention of physicists once more to optics,
    the science of light, which was now regarded as a form
    of electricity that could be reduced to the mechanics
    of a curious, rigid, but invisible medium known as the
    ether, which, at the time, was supposed to permeate
    the atmosphere, interstellar space and all transparent
    materials. Clerk Maxwell’s work on optics consisted in
    the mathematical development of ideas which had
    been previously expressed in a cogent but non-mathematical form by Faraday. The study of ether raised
    certain questions whose answers were obscure, as, for
    example, that of the motion of matter through the ether.
    The famous experiment of Michelson and Morley, in
    the nineties, was undertaken to resolve this problem,
    and it gave the entirely unexpected answer that there
    simply was no way to determine the motion of matter
    through the ether.
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    20
    TilE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    The first satisfactory solution to the problems aroused
    by this experiment was that of Lorentz, who pointed
    out that if the forces holding matter together were conceived as being themselves electrical or optical in
    nature, we should expect a negative result from the
    Michelson-Morley experiment. However, Einstein in
    1905 translated these ideas of Lorentz into a form in
    which the unobservability of absolute motion was rather
    a postulate of physics than the result of any particular
    structure of matter. For our purposes, the important
    thing is that in Einstein’s work, light and matter are
    on an equal basis, as they had been in the writings
    llefore Newton; without the Newtonian subordination
    of everything else to matter and mechanics.
    In explaining his views, Einstein makes abundant
    use of the observer who may be at rest or may be
    moving. In his theory of relativity it is impossible to
    introduce the observer without also introducing the
    idea of message, and without, in fact, returning the
    emphasis of physics to a quasi-Leibnitzian state, whose
    tendency is once again optical. Einstein’s theory of relativity and Gibbs’ statistical mechanics are in sharp
    contrast, in that Einstein, like Newton, is still talking
    primarily in terms of an absolutely rigid dynamics not
    introducing the idea of probability. Gibbs’ work, on
    the other hand, is probabilistic from the very start, yet
    both directions of work represent a shift in the point
    of view of physics in which the world as it actually
    exists is replaced in some sense or other by the world
    as it happens to be observed, and the old naive realism
    of physics gives way to something on which Bishop
    Berkeley might have smiled with pleasure.
    At this point it is appropriate for us to review certain
    notions pertaining to entropy which have already been
    presented in the introduction. As we have said, the
    idea of entropy represents several of the most important departures of Gibbsian mechanics from Newtonian mechanics. In Gibbs’ view we have a physical
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    21
    quantity which belongs not to the outside world as
    such, but to certain sets of possible outside worlds, and
    therefore to the answer to certain specific questions
    which we can ask concerning the outside world.
    Physics now becomes not the discussion of an outside
    universe which may be regarded as the total answer
    to all the questions concerning it, but an account of
    the answers to much more limited questions. In fact,
    we are now no longer concerned with the study of all
    possible outgoing and incoming messages which we
    may send and receive, but with the theory of much
    more specific outgoing and incoming messages; and it
    involves a measurement of the no-longer infinite amount
    of information that they yield us.
    Messages are themselves a form of pattern and organization. Indeed, it is possible to treat sets of messages as having an entropy like sets of states of the
    external world. Just as entropy is a measure of disorganization, the information carried by a set of messages is a measure of organization. In fact, it is possible
    to interpret the information carried by a message as
    essentially the negative of its entropy, and the negative
    logarithm of its probability. That is, the more probable
    the message, the less information it gives. Cliches, for
    example, are less illuminating than great poems.
    I have already referred to Leibnitz’s interest in
    automata, an interest incidentally shared by his contemporary, Pascal, who made real contributions to the
    development of what we now know as the desk addingmachine. Leibnitz saw in the concordance of the time
    given by clocks set at the same time, the model for the
    pre-established harmony of his monads. For the technique embodied in the automata of his time was that of
    the clockmaker. Let us consider the activity of the little
    figures which dance on the top of a music box. They
    move in accordance with a pattern, but it is a pattern
    which is set in advance, and in which the past activity
    of the figures has practically nothing to do with the
    22
    TilE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    pattern of their future activity. The probability that
    they will diverge from this pattern is nil. There is a
    message, indeed; but it goes from the machinery of
    the music box to the figures, and stops there. The figures themselves have no trace of communication with
    the outer world, except this one-way stage of communication with the pre-established mechanism of the music
    box. They are blind, deaf, and dumb, and cannot vary
    their activity in the least from the conventionalized
    pattern.
    Contrast with them the behavior of man, or indeed
    of any moderately intelligent animal such as a kitten.
    I call to the kitten and it looks up. I have sent it a
    message which it has received by its sensory organs,
    and which it registers in action. The kitten is hungry
    and lets out a pitiful wail. This time it is the sender of
    a message. The kitten bats at a swinging spool. The
    spool swings to its left, and the kitten catches it with
    its left paw. This time messages of a very complicated
    nature are both sent and received within the kitten’s
    own nervous system through certain nerve end-bodies
    in its joints, muscles, and tendons; and by means of
    nervous messages sent by these organs, the animal is
    aware of the actual position and tensions of its tissues.
    It is only through these organs that anything like a
    manual skill is possible.
    I have contrasted the prearranged behavior of the
    little figures on the music box on the one hand, and the
    contingent behavior of human beings and animals on
    the other. But we must not suppose that the music box
    is typical of all machine behavior.
    The older machines, and in particular the older attempts to produce automata, did in fact function on a
    closed clockwork basis. But modern automatic machines such as the controlled missile, the proximity
    fuse, the automatic door opener, the control apparatus
    for a chemical factory, and the rest of the modern
    armory of automatic machines which perform military
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    or industrial functions, possess sense organs; that is,
    receptors for messages coming from the outside. These
    may be as simple as photoelectric cells which change
    electrically when a light falls on them, and which can
    tell light from dark, or as complicated as a television
    set. They may measure a tension by the change it produces in the conductivity of a wire exposed to it, or
    they may measure temperature by means of a thermocouple, which is an instrument consisting of two distinct metals in contact with one another through which
    a current Haws when one of the points of contact is
    heated. Every instrument in the repertory of the
    scientific-instrument maker is a possible sense organ,
    and may be made to record its reading remotely
    through the intervention of appropriate electrical apparahls. Thus the machine which is conditioned by
    its relation to the external world, and by the things
    happening in the external world, is with us and has
    been with us for some time.
    The machine which acts on the external world by
    means of messages is also familiar. The automatic photoelectric door opener is known to every person who has
    passed through the Pennsylvania Station in New York,
    and is used in many other buildings as well. When a
    message consisting of the interception of a beam of
    light is sent to the apparatus, this message actuates the
    door, and opens it so that the passenger may go through.
    The steps between the actuation of a machine of
    this type by sense organs and its performance of a
    task may be as simple as in the case of the electric
    door; or it may be in fact of any desired degree of
    complexity within the limits of our engineering techniques. A complex action is one in which the data
    introduced, which we call the input, to obtain an effect
    on the outer world, which we call the output, may
    involve a large number of combinations. These are
    combinations, both of the data put in at the moment
    and of the records taken from the past stored data
    24
    TilE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    which we call the memory. These are recorded in the
    machine. The most complicated machines yet made
    which transform input data into output data are the
    high-speed electrical computing machines, of which I
    shall speak later in more detail. The determination of
    the mode of conduct of these machines is given through
    a special sort of input, which frequently consists of
    punched cards or tapes or of magnetized wires, and
    which determines the way in which the machine is going to act in one operation, as distinct from the way in
    which it might have acted in another. Because of the
    frequent use of punched or magnetic tape in the control, the data which are fed in, and which indicate the
    mode of operation of one of these machines for combining information, are called the taping.
    I have said that man and the animal have a kinaesthetic sense, by which they keep a record of the
    position and tensions of their muscles. For any machine
    subject to a varied external environment to act effectively it is necessary that information concerning the
    results of its own action be furnished to it as part of the
    information on which it must continue to act. For example, if we are running an elevator, it is not enough
    to open the outside door because the orders we have
    given should make the elevator be at that door at the
    time we open it. It is important that the release for
    opening the door be dependent on the fact that the
    elevator is actually at the door; otherwise something
    might have detained it, and the passenger might step
    into the empty shaft. This control of a machine on the
    basis of its actual performance rather than its expected
    performance is known as feedback, and involves sensory members which are actuated by motor members
    and perform the function of tell-tales or monitorsthat is, of elements which indicate a performance. It
    is the function of these mechanisms to control the mechanical tendency toward disorganization; in other
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    zs
    words, to produce a temporary and local reversal of
    the normal direction of entropy.
    I have just mentioned the elevator as an example of
    feedback. There are other cases where the importance
    of feedback is even more apparent. For example, a
    gun-pointer takes information from his instruments of
    observation, and conveys it to the gun, so that the
    latter will point in such a direction that the missile will
    pass through the moving target at a certain time. Now,
    the gun itself must be used under all conditions of
    weather. In some of these the grease is warm, and the
    gun swings easily and rapidly. Under other conditions
    the grease is frozen or mixed with sand, and the gun
    is slow to answer the orders given to it. If these orders
    are reinforced by an extra push given when the gun
    fails to respond easily to the orders and lags behind
    them, then the error of the gun-pointer will be decreased. To obtain a performance as uniform as possible, it is customary to put into the gun a control feedback element which reads the lag of the gun behind
    the position it should have according to the orders
    given it, and which uses this difference to give the gun
    an extra push.
    It is true that precautions must be taken so that the
    push is not too hard, for if it is, the gun will swing past
    its proper position, and will have to be pulled back in a
    series of oscillations, which may well become wider
    and wider, and lead to a disastrous instability. If the
    feedback system is itself controlled-if, in other words,
    its own entropic tendencies are checked by still other
    controlling mechanisms-and kept within limits sufficiently stringent, this will not occur, and the existence
    of the feedback will increase the stability of performance of the gun. In other words, the performance will
    become less dependent on the frictional load; or what
    is the same thing, on the drag created by the stiffness
    of the grease.
    Something very similar to this occurs in human action.
    z6
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    If I pick up my cigar, I do not will to move any specific
    muscles. Indeed in many cases, I do not know what
    those muscles are. What I do is to turn into action a
    certain feedback mechanism; namely, a reflex in which
    the amount by which I have yet failed to pick up the
    cigar is turned into a new and increased order to the
    lagging muscles, whichever they may be. In this way,
    a fairly uniform voluntary command will enable the
    same task to be performed from widely varying initial positions, and irrespective of the decrease of contraction due to fatigue of the muscles. Similarly, when
    I drive a car, I do not follow out a series of commands
    dependent simply on a mental image of the road and
    the task I am doing. If I find the car swerving too much
    to the right, that causes me to pull it to the left. This
    depends on the actual performance of the car, and not
    simply on the road; and it allows me to drive with
    nearly equal efficiency a light Austin or a heavy truck,
    without having formed separate habits for the driving
    of the two. I shall have more to say about this in the
    chapter in this book on special machines, where we
    shall discuss the service that can be done to neuropathology by the study of machines with defects in performance similar to those occurring in the human
    mechanism.
    It is my thesis that the physical functioning of the
    living individual and the operation of some of the newer
    communication machines are precisely parallel in their
    analogous attempts to control entropy through feedback. Both of them have sensory receptors as one stage
    in their cycle of operation: that is, in both of them
    there exists a special apparatus for collecting information from the outer world at low energy levels, and
    for making it available in the operation of the individual or of the machine. In both cases these external
    messages are not taken neat, but through the internal
    transforming powers of the apparatus, whether it be
    alive or dead. The information is then turned into a
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    27
    new form available for the further stages of performance. In both the animal and the machine this performance is made to be effective on the outer world.
    In both of them, their performed action on the outer
    world, and not merely their intended action, is reported back to the central regulatory apparatus. This
    complex of behavior is ignored by the average man,
    and in particular does not play the role that it should
    in our habitual analysis of society; for just as individual physical responses may be seen from this point of
    view, so may the organic responses of society itself. I
    do not mean that the sociologist is unaware of the existence and complex nature of communications in
    society, but until recently he has tended to overlook the
    extent to which they are the cement which binds its
    fabric together.
    We have seen in this chapter the fundamental unity
    of a complex of ideas which until recently had not
    been sufficiently associated with one another, namely,
    the contingent view of physics that Gibbs introduced
    as a modification of the traditional, Newtonian conventions, the Augustinian attitude toward order and
    conduct which is demanded by this view, and the
    theory of the message among men, machines, and in
    society as a sequence of events in time which, though
    it itself has a certain contingency, strives to hold back
    nature’s tendency toward disorder by adjusting its
    parts to various purposive ends.
    D
    PROGRESS AND ENTROPY
    As we have said, nature·s statistical tendency to disorder, the tendency for entropy to increase in isolated
    systems, is expressed by the second law of thermodynamics. We, as human beings, are not isolated systems. We take in food, which generates energy, from
    the outside, and are, as a result, parts of that larger
    world which contains those sources of our vitality. But
    even more important is the fact that we take in information through our sense organs, and we act on information received
    Now the physicist is already familiar with the signif:
    icance of this statement as far as it concerns our relations with the environment. A brilliant expression of
    the role of information in this respect is provided by
    Clerk Maxwell, in the form of the so-called “Maxwell
    demon,” which we may describe as follows.
    Suppose that we have a container of gas, whose temperature is everywhere the same. Some molecules of
    this gas will be moving faster than others. Now let us
    suppose that there is a little door in the container that
    let~ the gas into a tube which runs to a heat engine,
    and that the exhaust of this heat engine is connected
    by another tube back to the gas chamber, through another door. At each door there is a little being with the
    power of watching the on-coming molecules and of
    opening or closing the doors in accordance with their
    velocity.
    The demon at the first door opens it only for highspeed molecules and closes it in the face of low-speed
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    29
    molecules coming from the container. The role of the
    demon at the second door is exactly the opposite: he
    opens the door only for low-speed molecules coming
    from the container and closes it in the face of highspeed molecules. The result is that the temperature
    goes up at one end and down at the other thus creating
    a perpetual motion of “the second kind,: that is, a
    perpetual motion which does not violate the first law
    of thermodynamics, which tells us that the amount of
    energy within a given system is constant, but does
    violate the second law of thermodynamics, which tells
    us that energy spontaneously runs down hill in temperature. In other words, the Maxwell demon seems to
    overcome the tendency of entropy to increase.
    Perhaps I can illustrate this idea still further by considering a crowd milling around in a subway at two
    turnstiles, one of which will only let people out if they
    are observed to be running at a certain speed, and the
    other of which will only let people out if they are
    moving slowly. The fortuitous movement of the people
    in the subway will show itself as a stream of fast-moving
    people coming from the first turnstile, whereas the second turnstile will only let through slow-moving people.
    If these two turnstiles are connected by a passageway
    with a treadmill in it, the fast-moving people will have
    a greater tendency to turn the treadmill in one direction than the slow people to tum it in the other, and we
    shall gather a source of useful energy in the fortuitous
    milling around of the crowd.
    Here there emerges a very interesting distinction
    between the physics of our grandfathers and that of
    the present day. In nineteenth century physics, it
    seemed to cost nothing to get information. The result is
    that there is nothing in Maxwell’s physics to prevent
    one of his demons from furnishing its own power source.
    Modern physics, however, recognizes that the demon
    can only gain the information with which it opens or
    closes the door from something like a sense organ
    30
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    which for these purposes is an eye. The light that
    strikes the demon’s eye is not an energy-less supplement of mechanical motion, but shares in the main
    properties of mechanical motion itself. Light cannot be
    received by any instrument unless it hits it, and cannot
    indicate the position of any particle unless it hits the
    particle as well. This means, then, that even from a
    purely mechanical point of view we cannot consider
    the gas chamber as containing mere gas, but rather gas
    and light which may or may not be in equilibrium. If
    the gas and the light are in equilibrium, it can be shown
    as a consequence of present physical doctrine that the
    Maxwell demon will be as blind as if there were no
    light at all. We shall have a cloud of light coming from
    every direction, giving no indication of the position and
    momenta of the gas particles. Therefore the Maxwell
    demon will work only in a system that is not in equilibrium. In such a system, however, it will turn out
    that the constant collision between light and gas particles tends to bring the light and particles to an equilibrium. Thus while the demon may temporarily reverse the usual direction of entropy, ultimately it too
    will wear down.
    The Maxwell demon can work indefinitely only if
    additional light comes from outside the system and
    does not correspond in temperature to the mechanical
    temperature of the particles themselves. This is a
    situation which should be perfectly familiar to us, because we see the universe around us reflecting light
    from the sun, which is very far from being in equilibrium with mechanical systems on the earth. Strictly
    speaking, we are confronting particles whose temperature is so or oo· F. with a light which comes from a
    sun at many thousands of degrees.
    In a system which is not in equilibrium, or in part
    of such a system, entropy need not increase. It may,
    in fact, decrease locally. Perhaps this non-equilibrium
    of the world about us is merely a stage in a downhill
    31
    course which will ultimately lead to equilibrium. Sooner
    or later we shall die, and it is highly probable that the
    whole universe around us will die the heat death, in
    which the world shall be reduced to one vast temperature equilibrium in which nothing really new ever
    happens. There will be nothing left but a drab uniformity out of which we can expect only minor and
    insignificant local fluctuations.
    But we are not yet spectators at the last stages of
    the world’s death. In fact these last stages can have
    no spectators. Therefore, in the world with which we
    are immediately concerned there are stages which,
    though they occupy an insignificant fraction of eternity, are of great significance for our purposes, for in
    them entropy does not increase and organization and
    its correlative, information, are being built up.
    What I have said about these enclaves of increasing
    organization is not confined merely to organization as
    exhibited by living beings. Machines also contribute
    to a local and temporary building up of information,
    notwithstanding their crude and imperfect organization compared with that of ourselves.
    Here I want to interject the semantic point that such
    words as life, purpose, and soul are grossly inadequate
    to precise scientific thinking. These terms have gained
    their significance through our recognition of the unity
    of a certain group of phenomena, and do not in fact
    furnish us with any adequate basis to characterize this
    unity. Whenever we find a new phenomenon which
    partakes to some degree of the nature of those which
    we have already termed “living phenomena,” but does
    not conform to all the associated aspects which define
    the term “life,” we are faced with the problem whether
    to enlarge the word “life” so as to include them, or
    to define it in a more restrictive way so as to exclude
    them. We have encountered this problem in the past
    in considering viruses, which show some of the tend~
    encies of life-to persist, to multiply, and to organizeCYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    32
    THE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    but do not express these tendencies in a fully-developed form. Now that certain analogies of behavior are
    being observed between the machine and the living
    organism, the problem as to whether the machine is
    alive or not is, for our purposes, semantic and we are
    at liberty to answer it one way or the other as best suits
    our convenience. As Humpty Dumpty says about some
    of his more remarkable words, “I pay them extra, and
    make them dow hat I want.”
    If we wish to use the word “life” to cover all phenomena which locally swim upstream against the
    current of increasing entropy, we are at liberty to do
    so. However, we shall then include many astronomical
    phenomena which have only the shadiest resemblance
    to life as we ordinarily know it. It is in my opinion,
    therefore, best to avoid all question-begging epithets
    such as “life,” ”soul,” “vitalism,” and the like, and say
    merely in connection with machines that there is no
    reason why they may not resemble human beings in
    representing pockets of decreasing entropy in a framework in which the large entropy tends to increase.
    When I compare the living organism with such a
    machine, I do not for a moment mean that the specific
    physical, chemical, and spiritual processes of life as we
    ordinarily know it are the same as those of life-imitating machines. I mean simply that they both can exemplify locally anti-entropic processes, which perhaps
    may also be exemplified in many other ways which we
    should naturally term neither biological nor mechanical.
    While it is impossible to make any universal statements concerning life-imitating automata in a field
    which is growing as rapidly as that of automatization,
    there are some general features of these machines as
    they actually exist that I should like to emphasize. One
    is that they are machines to perform some definite task
    or tasks, and therefore must possess effector organs
    (analogous to arms and legs in human beings) with
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    33
    which such tasks can be performed. The second point
    is that they must be en rapport with the outer world
    by sense organs, such as photoelectric cells and thermometers, which not only tell them what the existing
    circumstances are, but enable them to record the performance or nonperformance of their own tasks. This
    last function, as we have seen, is called feedback, the
    property of being able to adjust future conduct by past
    performance. Feedback may be as simple as that of the
    common reflex, or it may be a higher order feedback,
    in which past experience is used not only to regulate
    specific movements, but also whole policies of behavior. Such a policy-feedback may, and often does,
    appear to be what we know under one aspect as a
    conditioned reflex, and under another as learning.
    For all these forms of behavior, and particularly for
    the more complicated ones, we must have central decision organs which determine what the machine is to
    do next on the basis of information fed back to it, which
    it stores by means analogous to the memory of a living
    organism.
    It is easy to make a simple machine which will run
    toward the light or run away from it, and if such machines also contain lights of their own, a number of
    them together will show complicated forms of social
    behavior such as have been described by Dr. Grey
    Walter in his book, The Living Brain. At present the
    more complicated machines of this type are nothing
    but scientific toys for the exploration of the possibilities of the machine itself and of its analogue, the nervous system. But there is reason to anticipate that the
    developing technology of the near future will use some
    of these potentialities.
    Thus the nervous system and the automatic machine
    are fundamentally alike in that they are devices which
    make decisions on the basis of decisions they have
    made in the past. The simplest mechanical devices will
    make decisions between two alternatives, such as the
    34
    TilE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    closing or opening of a switch. In the nervous system,
    the individual nerve fiber also decides between carrying an impulse or not. In both the machine and the
    nerve, there is a specific apparatus for making future
    decisions depend on past decisions, and in the nervous
    system a large part of this task is done at those extremely complicated points called “synapses” where a
    number of incoming nerve fibers connect with a single
    outgoing nerve fiber. In many cases it is possible to
    state the basis of these decisions as a threshold of action
    of the synapse, or in other words, by telling how many
    incoming fibers should fire in order that the outgoing
    fibers may fire.
    This is the basis of at least part of the analogy between machines and living organisms. The synapse in
    the living organism corresponds to the switching device in the machine. For further development of the
    detailed relationship between machines and living
    organisms, one should consult the extremely inspiring
    books of Dr. Walter and Dr. W. Ross Ashby. 1
    The machine, like the living organism, is, as I have
    said, a device which locally and temporarily seems to
    resist the general tendency for the increase of entropy.
    By its ability to make decisions it can produce around
    it a local zone of organization in a world whose general
    tendency is to run down.
    The scientist is always working to discover the order
    and organization of the universe, and is thus playing
    a game against the arch enemy, disorganization. Is this
    devil Manichaean or Augustinian? Is it a contrary force
    opposed to order or is it the very absence of order
    itself? The difference between these two sorts of demons
    will make itself apparent in the tactics to be used
    against them. The Manichaean devil is an opponent,
    1 W. Ross Ashby, Design for a Brain, Wiley, New York,
    1952, and W. Grey Walter, The Limng Brain, Norton, New
    York, 1953·
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    35
    like any other opponent, who is detennined on victory
    and will use any trick of craftiness or dissimulation to
    obtain this victory. In particular, he will keep his policy
    of confusion secret, and if we show any signs of beginning to discover his policy, he will change it in order
    to keep us in the dark. On the other hand, the Augustinian devil, which is not a power in itself, but the
    measure of our own weakness, may require our full
    resources to uncover, but when we have uncovered it,
    we have in a certain sense exorcised it, and it will not
    alter its policy on a matter already decided with the
    mere intention of confounding us further. The Manichaean devil is playing a game of poker against us
    and will resort readily to bluffing; which, as von Neumann explains in his Theory of Games, is intended not
    merely to enable us to win on a bluff, but to prevent the
    other side from winning on the basis of a certainty
    that we will not bluff.
    Compared to this Manichaean being of renned malice, the Augustinian devil is stupid. He plays a difficult
    game, but he may be defeated by our intelligence as
    thoroughly as by a sprinkle of holy water.
    As to the nature of the devil, we have an aphorism
    of Einstein’s which is more than an aphorism, and is
    really a statement concerning the foundations of scientinc method. ‘”The Lord is subtle, but he isn’t simply
    mean.” Here the word ‘”Lord” is used to describe those
    forces in nature which include what we have attributed to his very humble servant, the Devil, and
    Einstein means to say that these forces do not bluff.
    Perhaps this devil is not far in meaning from Mephistopheles. When Faust asked Mephistopheles what he
    was, Mephistopheles replied, ‘”A part of that force
    which always seeks evil and always does good.” In
    other words, the devil is not unlimited in his ability
    to deceive, and the scientist who looks for a positive
    force determined to confuse us in the universe which
    he is investigating is wasting his time. Nature offers
    36
    TilE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    resistance to decoding, but it does not show ingenuity
    in finding new and undecipherable methods for jamming our communication with the outer world.
    This distinction between the passive resistance of
    nature and the active resistance of an opponent suggests a distinction between the research scientist and
    the warrior or the game player. The research physicist
    has all the time in the world to carry out his experiments, and he need not fear that nature will in time
    discover his tricks and method and change her policy.
    Therefore, his work is governed by his best moments,
    whereas a chess player cannot make one mistake without finding an alert adversary ready to take advantage
    of it and to defeat him. Thus the chess player is governed more by his worst moments than by his best
    moments. I may be prejudiced about this claim: for I
    have found it possible myself to do effective work in
    science, while my chess has been continually vitiated
    by my carelessness at critical instants.
    The scientist is thus disposed to regard his opponent
    as an honorable enemy. This attitude is necessary for
    his effectiveness as a scientist, but tends to make him
    the dupe of unprincipled people in war and in politics.
    It also has the effect of making it hard for the general
    public to understand him, for the general public is
    much more concerned with personal antagonists than
    with nature as an antagonist.
    We are immersed in a life in which the world as a
    whole obeys the second law of thermodynamics: confusion increases and order decreases. Yet, as we have
    seen, the second law of thermodynamics, while it may
    be a valid statement about the whole of a closed
    system, is definitely not valid concerning a non-isolated
    part of it. There are local and temporary islands of
    decreasing entropy in a world in which the entropy as
    a whole tends to increase. and the existence of these islands enables some of us to assert the existence of progress. What can we say about the general direction of
    CYBERNETICS AND SOCIETY
    37
    the battle between progress and increasing entropy in
    the world immediately about us?
    The Enlightenment, as we all know, fostered the
    idea of progress, even though there were among the
    men of the eighteenth century some who felt that this
    progress was subject to a law of diminishing returns,
    and that the Golden Age of society would not differ
    very much from what they saw about them. The crack
    in the fabric of the Enlightenment, marked by the
    French Revolution, was accompanied by doubts of
    progress elsewhere. Malthus, for example, sees the cui~
    ture of his age about to sink into the slough of an un~
    controlled increase in population, swallowing up all
    the gains so far made by humanity.
    The line of intellectual descent from Malthus to Dar~
    win is clear. Darwin’s great innovation in the theory of
    evolution was that he conceived of it not as a
    Lamarckian spontaneous ascent from higher to higher
    and from better to better, but as a phenomenon in
    which living beings showed (a) a spontaneous tend~
    ency to develop in many directions, and (b) a tend~
    ency to follow the pattern of their ancestors. The
    combination of these two effects was to prune an over~
    lush developing nature and to deprive it of those or~
    ganisms which were ill-adapted to their environment,
    by a process of “natural selection.” The result of this
    pruning was to leave a residual pattern of forms of
    life more or less well adapted to their environment.
    This residual pattern, according to Darwin, assumes
    the appearance of universal purposiveness.
    The concept of a residual pattern has come to the
    fore again in the work of Dr. W. Ross Ashby. He uses
    it to explain the concept of machines that learn. He
    points out that a machine of rather random and hap~
    hazard structure will have certain near-equilibrium
    positions, and certain positions far from equilibrium,
    and that the near-equilibrium patterns will by their
    very nature last for a long time, while the others will
    38
    TilE HUMAN USE OF HUMAN BEINGS
    appear only temporarily. The result is that in Ashby’s
    machine, as in Darwin’s nature, we have the appearance of a purposefulness in a system which is not purposefully constructed simply because purposelessness
    is in its very nature transitory. Of course, in the long
    run, the great trivial purpose of maximum entropy will
    appear to be the most enduring of all. But in the intermediate stages an organism or a society of organisms will tend to dally longer in those modes of activity
    in which the different parts work together, according to
    a more or less meaningful pattern.
    I believe that Ashby’s brilliant idea of the unpurposeful random mechanism which seeks for its own
    purpose through a process of learning is not only one of
    the great philosophical contributions of the present
    day, but will lead to highly useful technical developments in the task of au…

    Calculate your order
    275 words
    Total price: $0.00

    Top-quality papers guaranteed

    54

    100% original papers

    We sell only unique pieces of writing completed according to your demands.

    54

    Confidential service

    We use security encryption to keep your personal data protected.

    54

    Money-back guarantee

    We can give your money back if something goes wrong with your order.

    Enjoy the free features we offer to everyone

    1. Title page

      Get a free title page formatted according to the specifics of your particular style.

    2. Custom formatting

      Request us to use APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, or any other style for your essay.

    3. Bibliography page

      Don’t pay extra for a list of references that perfectly fits your academic needs.

    4. 24/7 support assistance

      Ask us a question anytime you need to—we don’t charge extra for supporting you!

    Calculate how much your essay costs

    Type of paper
    Academic level
    Deadline
    550 words

    How to place an order

    • Choose the number of pages, your academic level, and deadline
    • Push the orange button
    • Give instructions for your paper
    • Pay with PayPal or a credit card
    • Track the progress of your order
    • Approve and enjoy your custom paper

    Ask experts to write you a cheap essay of excellent quality

    Place an order